Advertisement

The Classical Biological Theory of Knowledge

  • Milič Čapek
Chapter
Part of the Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science book series (BSPS, volume 7)

Abstract

‘Anti-intellectualism’ is a label frequently applied to Bergson’s philosophical thought, but only rarely is the meaning of this term properly understood and fully clarified. It is generally not realized, or at least not sufficiently stressed, that his alleged anti–intellectualism is opposed only to a certain, though historically the most important and still the most dominant, form of human intellect; that is, to what he himself called the ‘logic of solid bodies’ and what, perhaps more appropriately, may be called the Newton–Euclidian form of intellect. This form, as Bergson stressed, is a result of a long evolutionary process the duration of which certainly transcends the duration of the human species. This duration itself is the ground for its practical justification and its approximate applicability to our ordinary daily experience; but when we are confronted with the new types of experience which do not fit the traditional patterns of thought, a new and fresh effort is required to create more flexible and more adequate forms of understanding. Although Bergson’s language is not always as specific as we would wish to have it, the meaning of his anti–intellectualism is unmistakably clear for an attentive and unprejudiced reader, especially as he becomes aware that it is an organic part of Bergson’s biological theory of knowledge. In my opinion no fruitful study of Bergson’s thought, and, in particular, no true understanding of his sometimes paradoxical philosophy of nature is possible without taking his biologically oriented epistemology into consideration.

Keywords

Human Mind Modern Physic Euclidian Geometry Newtonian Mechanic Biological Theory 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 1.
    Ch. Singer,A Short History of Scientific Ideas to 1900, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1959, p. 512–513.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Henry D. Aiken,The Age of Ideology. The Nineteenth Century Philosophers, New York 1956, p. 170.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    C.M., p. 10–13; 109. Spencer’s influence was rightly stressed by Albert Thibaudet,Le Bergsonisme, Paris 1923, II, p. 218.Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    C.E., p. XXIII.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    H. Spencer,First Principles, 4th Ed., Appleton, New York, 1896, pp. 86–87.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    The Principles of Psychology, 3rd Ed., Appleton, New York, 1897, 1, pp. 318–319.Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    H. Taine,Les origines de la France contemporaine, 34th Ed., Paris, 1947, 1, p. 270.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    M. Berthelot,Les origines de l’alchemie, Paris 1885, p. 151.Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    Dialogues of Alfred North Whitehead as Recorded by Lucien Price, New American Library, New York, 1960, p. 12.Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    B. Russell, ‘A Free Man’s Worship’, in:Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays, Pelican Books, 1953, p. 51.Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    The Principles of Psychology, II, 1, p. 195.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    H. Taine,De I’intelligence, 16th Ed., Paris 1927, 1, p. 236.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    H. Spencer,First Principles, Appleton, New York, 1896, Chapters VII and VIII, in particular pp. 203–204; 229–231; W. Ostwald,Vorlesungen über Naturphilosophie, Leipzig 1902, p. 296;Grundriss der Naturphilosophie, Leipzig 1919, p. 144.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland 1971

Authors and Affiliations

  • Milič Čapek

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations