Skip to main content

Abstract

During de Raey’s professorship at Leiden, the university emerged as an important center for the dispersion of Cartesianism throughout northern Europe, a role that was further enhanced in the 1660’s by the presence at Leiden of Arnold Geulincx.1 A convert from Catholicism, Geulincx had come to Leiden from Lou vain in 1658.2 Supported by the theologian Abraham Heidanus, he was appointed lector in logic in 1662 and three years later acquired the title of professor. Although he held that title ostensibly with the understanding that he would adhere to the peripatetic philosophy,3 he was a dedicated Cartesian whose writings were to have a considerable impact in the following decades. The subjects for which he was formally responsible at Leiden were logic and ethics,4 outside of which his major influence was in the realm of metaphysics. Nonetheless, physics was neglected neither in his writings nor teaching, and he bolstered the dominance that de Raey had already acquired for Cartesian natural philosophy within the university.5

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. De Raey’s former students were particularly influential in the spread of Cartesianism in Germany. See Heinz Schneppen, Niederländische Universitäten und Deutsches Geistesleben, von der Gründung der Universität Leiden bis ins späte 18. Jahrhundert (Münster, Westfalen: Aschendorff, 1960), pp. 76–8. Bohatec, Die cartesianische Scholastik, pp. 51 and 78. Beck, Early German Philosophy, pp. 183–4.

    Google Scholar 

  2. On Geulincx, see J. P. N. Land, Arnold Geulincx und seine Philosophie (Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1895)

    Google Scholar 

  3. On Geulincx, see J. P. N. Land, “Arnold Geulincx te Leiden (1658–1669),” Mededeelingen, Kon. Akademie van Wetenschappen, Amsterdam, Afdeeling Letterkunde, series 3, Vol. Ill (1887), pp. 277–327

    Google Scholar 

  4. On Geulincx, see J. P. N. Land, “Arnold Geulincx and His Works,” Mind, Vol. XVI, pp. 223–42. (1887) Victor Vander Haeghen, Geulincx: Étude sur sa vie, sa philosophie et ses ouvrages (Gand: Ad. Hoste, 1886).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Land, “Geulincx te Leiden,” p. 315.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Bronnen, Vol. III, pp. 179* and 210*; see also the Series Lectionum for the years 1663–9. Land, op. cit., p. 318.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See his Sämtliche Schriften in fünf Bänden, ed. H. J. de Vleeschauwer (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Friedrich Frommann, 1965–68).

    Google Scholar 

  8. The Correspondence of Henry Oldenburg, ed. and trans. A. Rupert Hall and Marie Boas Hall (Madison, etc.: University of Wisconsin Press, 1965), Vol. V, p. 141.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Bronnen, Vol. III, pp. 236 and 245. Sassen, Geschiedenis van de Wijsbegeerte in Nederland, p. 159.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Suringar, “De Leidsehe Hoogleeraren in de natuurkundige Wetenschappen, inzonderheid in de Kruid- en Scheikunde, na den Dood van Sylvius en vóór Boerhaave’s Benoeming tot Professor Chemiae (1672–1718),” in Bijdragen tot de Geschiedenis van het Geneeskundig Onderwijs aan de Leidsche Hoogeschool, p. 18. At Leiden, as at other continental universities, the degree of doctor of philosophy appeared as an equivalent to the master of arts in the course of the seventeenth century; Morison, The Founding of Harvard College, p. 145, n. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See Bohatec, Die cartesianische Scholastik, passim, and Cramer, Abraham Heidanus.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See John B. Wolf, Louis XIV (New York: W. W. Norton and Company, Inc., c. 1968), p. 213 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Pieter Geyl, The Netherlands in the Seventeenth Century, Part Two 1648–1715 (London: Ernest Beim Ltd.; New York: Barnes and Noble, Inc., c. 1964), p. 121 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Directly in the path of the French advance, Leiden had distinguished itself among the other cities of the province of Holland by its willingness to accept the humiliating French terms for surrender; Stephen B. Baxter, William III and the Defense of European Liberty, 1650–1702 (New York: Harcourt, Brace and World, Inc., c. 1966), pp. 75

    Google Scholar 

  15. Directly in the path of the French advance, Leiden had distinguished itself among the other cities of the province of Holland by its willingness to accept the humiliating French terms for surrender; Stephen B. Baxter, William III and the Defense of European Liberty, 1650–1702 (New York: Harcourt, Brace and World, Inc., c. 1966), pp. 77.

    Google Scholar 

  16. See Bohatec, Die cartesianische Scholastik.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Sassen, Geschiedenis van de Wijsbegeerte in Nederland, pp. 141–2. Cramer, Abraham Heidanus, p. 120; but see also pp. 43 and 76.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Bronnen, Vol. III, pp. 271 and 274–8.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Suringar, “Invloed der Cartesiaansche Wijsbegeerte op het natuur- en geneeskundig Onderwijs aan de Leidsche hoogeschool,” p. 29.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Bronnen, Vol. III, pp. 278 and 290–1.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., pp. 280 and 291–3.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., pp. 307, 319, 321, and 259*–60*. Sassen, Geschiedenis van de Wijsbegeerte in Nederland, p. 160. Concerning Wilhelmius, see also the Nieuw Nederlandsch Biografisch Woordenboek, Vol. V, 1125–6.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Bronnen, Vol. III, pp. 314–5.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid., pp. 312–3.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Nieuw Nederlandsch Biografisch Woordenboek, Vol. VIII, 888–9; Vol. X, 955.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Bronnen, Vol. III, pp. 317–21 and 259*.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Cramer, Abraham Heidanus, pp. 124–5.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid., p. 153 and passim.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid., pp. 153–4. Sassen, Geschiedenis van de Wijsbegeerte in Nederland, p. 162. Thijssen-Schoute, “Le cartésianisme aux Pays-Bas,” p. 208.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Dibon, “Notes bibliographiques,” p. 269, n. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Cramer, Abraham Heidanus, pp. 153–4.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Charles Borgeaud, Histoire de l’Université de Genève: L’Académie de Calvin, 1559–1798 (Genève: Georg et Co., 1900), pp. 406–12.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Bronnen, Vol. III, p. 245. Senguerdius was offering lectures and experimental demonstrations pertaining to physics at least by 1681; see the Series lectionum for that year, Ibid., p. 269*.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ibid., pp. 306* and 228.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Philosophia naturalis, quatuor partibus primarias corporum species, affectiones, differentias, productiones, mutationes, et interitus, exhibens (2nd ed.; Lugduni Batavorum: Apud Danielem à Gaesbeeck, 1685), “Ad lectorem.”

    Google Scholar 

  37. All references will be to the second edition, cited immediately above.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Philosophia naturalis, p. 7 ff. and 20 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ibid., p. 160 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Ibid., p. 174 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  41. When de Volder was presiding in the lecture hall, however, a moving earth — or Descartes’ non-moving earth borne about by celestial currents — was also still openly and firmly defended at Leiden. See in particular the disputation of Gysbertus Henricus Casembroot, Disputatio philosophica quae est de mundi systemate, sub praesidio D. Burcheri de Volder (Lugduni Batavorum: Apud Abrahamum Elzevier, 1694).

    Google Scholar 

  42. Also Samuel Koleseri’s Disputatio philosophica inauguralis de systemate mundi, pro gradu doctoratus et liberalium artium magisterio (Lugduni Batavorum: Apud Viduam et Haeredes Johannis Elsevirii, 1681); “that system of the world delineated by the most noble Descartes,” reads one of the Annexa philosophica at the end, “is not to be held as a mere hypothesis, but as the truth of the matter itself.”

    Google Scholar 

  43. Philosophia naturalis, p. 76 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Ibid., p. 80.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Disputationes philosophicae sive cogitationes rationales de rerum naturalium principiis (Medioburgi: Typis Remigii Schreverii, 1681), p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Quaestiones academicae de aëris gravitate (Medioburgi: Typis Viduae Remigii Schreverii, 1681), p. 39.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Henricus van Bronchorst, Disputatio philosophica de vera gravitatis causa, sub praesidio Dni. Burcheri de Volder (Lugduni Batavorum: Apud Abrahamum Elzevier, 1685), p. VI.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid., p. V.

    Google Scholar 

  49. The Cartesians, of course, were hardly willing to concede this. De Volder’s student van Bronchorst also claimed in disputation that no objections could be raised against Descartes’s attribution of terrestrial gravity to the secondary vortex about the earth itself and the pressures resulting within the celestial fluid; this promised the clearest and easiest explanation, van Bronchorst declared (Ibid., p. VIII). This was, however, only one of at least three possible explanations that Descartes had considered. Compare articles XIX–XXIII, “Pars quarta,” of the Latin Principia philosophiae in the Opera philosophica (fourth edition) of Descartes published in Amsterdam in 1664 with the equivalent passages in the French edition of 1681, reproduced in Oeuvres de Descartes, ed. Victor Cousin (Paris: F. G. Levrault, 1824), Vol. III.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Sämtliche Schriften, Vol. II, p. 493.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Ibid., pp. 495–6.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Ibid., p. 496.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Exercitationes academicae, quibus Ren. Cartesii philosophia defenditur adversus Petri Danielis Huetii Episcopi Suessionensis Censurant philosophiae Cartesianae (Amstelaedami: Apud Arnoldum van Ravestein, 1695), p. 89 ff. in the second series of the pagination.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Ibid., pp. 90–1.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Philosophia naturalis, pp. 12–3.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Edward Grant, “Medieval and Seventeenth-Century Conceptions of an Infinite Void Space beyond the Cosmos,” Isis, Vol. LX (1969), pp. 48–51.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Institutiones physicae, Vol. I, pp. 59 and 306 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Disputationes philosophicae de rerum naturalium principiis, p. 141.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Ibid., p. 145.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Ibid., pp. 119–20.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Philosophia naturalis, pp. 152–3.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Ibid., pp. 156–7.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Grant, “Medieval and Seventeenth-Century Infinite Void Space,” passim.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Philosophia naturalis, p. 49 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Inquisitiones experimentales (2nd ed.; Lugduni Batavarum: Apud Cornelium Boutesteyn, 1699), p. 15; Rationis atque experientiae connubium (Roterodami: Apud Bernardum Bos, 1715), passim.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Institutiones physicae (rev. ed.; Lugduni Batavorum: Excudebat Vidua Ioannis Patij, 1624), p. 92.

    Google Scholar 

  67. conjunctio viciniae atque distantiae ejusdem ad idem (Sämtliche Schriften, Vol. II, p. 496).

    Google Scholar 

  68. Ibid., p. 498.

    Google Scholar 

  69. The potential relationship between the relativity of motion and concepts of full or empty space was first suggested to me by Richard S. Westfall.

    Google Scholar 

  70. loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Ibid., p. 390.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Ibid., p. 371.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Philosophia naturalis, pp. 34–5.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Johannes Bruno, Disputatio physica de motu, tertia et ultima, sub praesidio D. Burcheri de Volder (Lugduni Batavorum: Apud Viduam et Haeredes Joannis Elsevirii, 1675), pp. II—V.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Philosophia naturalis, pp. 29–31.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Ibid., p. 29.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Ibid., pp. 37 and 43 ff. Senguerdius argued that since the quantity of motion lost by one body which moved another would be acquired not only by the body moved but by its neighboring bodies as well, twice as much motion would result.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Sämtliche Schriften, Vol. II, pp. 513–5.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Jacobus Erckelens, Exercitationum philosophicarum tertia et vicesima, quae est de corpore, sub praesidio D. Burcheri de Volder (Lugduni Batavorum: Abrahamum Elzevier, 1692), corollary II.

    Google Scholar 

  81. See Hermannus Schuyl, Disputatio philosophica inauguralis de vi corporum elastica (Lugduni Batavorum: Apud Abrahamum Elzevier, 1688); this pro gradu disputation is dedicated to de Volder as the “principal founder of my studies.” See also Senguerdius, Philosophia naturalis, p. 42 ff. It has been observed that Descartes’ laws of impact were incorporated into the traditional physics with comparative ease

    Google Scholar 

  82. Pierre Boutroux, “L’Enseignement de la mécanique en France au XVIIe siècle,” Isis, Vol. IV (1921–2), pp. 286–7.

    Google Scholar 

  83. D. van Arkel, “Leids Studentenleven in de 16e, 17e, en 18e Eeuw,” in Geschiedboek van het Leidsche Studenten Corps (Leiden: H. E. Stenfert Kroese, 1950), p. 28.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1973 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ruestow, E.G. (1973). Passing Crises, Enduring Disagreement. In: Physics at Seventeenth and Eighteenth-Century Leiden: Philosophy and the New Science in the University. Archives Internationales D’histoire des Idees / International Archives of the History of Ideas, vol 11. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2463-1_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2463-1_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-247-1557-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-2463-1

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics