Skip to main content

Facts and Theories: Conventionalism

  • Chapter
  • 111 Accesses

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 35))

Abstract

In the last paragraphs of the previous chapter, we explained why we believe that Popper’s criticism of the radical empiricist solution of the problem of relation between facts and theories is correct. The Popperian point of view in this matter is, as we have noticed, a variant of conventionalism. Despite a number of interesting details in Popper’s proposals, his solution of this problem is not at all surprising: the criticism of the concept of ‘bare empirical facts’ is to be found within all conventionalist doctrines, in the writings of Poincaré1 and Duhem,2 as well as in the works of Adjukiewicz stemming from the period when he still held this position. We must remember, however, that Adjukiewicz did not abandon this criticism even when he gave up the position of conventionalism. As I do not believe either that the alternative to radical empiricism of some kind of conventionalism exhausts all the possibilities for solving the problem, I will now discuss it in more detail. With this intent I will first present Popper’s conventionalist solution of the problem of the relation between facts and theories and then, in the concluding paragraphs of this chapter, discuss in general terms the controversy between empiricism and conventionalism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. “It is often said that experiments should be made without preconceived ideas. That is impossible. Not only would it make every experiment fruitless, but even if we wished to do so, it could not be done. Every man has his own conception of the world, and this he cannot so easily lay aside. We must, for example, use language. And our language is necessarily steeped in preconceived ideas. Only they are unconscious, preconceived ideas which are a thousand times the most dangerous of all.” (H. Poincaré, Science and Hypothesis, New York 1952, p. 143.)

    Google Scholar 

  2. P. Duhem, Aim and Structure of Physical Theory, New York 1962.

    Google Scholar 

  3. K. R. Popper, Conjectures and Refutations, London 1969.

    Google Scholar 

  4. K. R. Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery, pp. 101–102.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Ibid., p. 86.

    Google Scholar 

  6. R. Carnap, Logical Foundations of Probability, Chicago 1951

    Google Scholar 

  7. H. Reichenbach, Experience and Prediction, Chicago 1938

    Book  Google Scholar 

  8. H. Reichenbach, The Rise of Scientific Philosophy, Berkeley 1951.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. also S. Amsterdamski, ‘O obiektywnych interpretacjach pojęcia prawdopodobieńtstwa’ (On the Objective Interpretations of the Concept of Probability) in Prawo, konieczność, prawdopodobieństwo, Warsaw 1964, pp. 1–125.

    Google Scholar 

  10. The possibility of the probabilistic estimation of scientific hypotheses is a matter for discussion. First of all, it may be doubted whether the Carnapian theory provides the possibility of a quantitative estimate of the degree of confirmation when the evidence, in respect to which we estimate the probability of a hypotheses, is not statistical. (S. Amsterdamski, op. cit. Part I). Secondly, even if this estimation is possible, it is irrelevant in respect to the truth of the estimated hypothesis. A false hypothesis which follows deductively from false premises has the probability p=l.

    Google Scholar 

  11. (Cf. S. Amsterdamski, ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  12. S. Amsterdamski, ‘Prawdziwość i prawiopodobieństwo’ (Truth and Probability), Zeszyty Naukowe Uniwersytetu Lodzkiego, 1967, pp. 1–15). Finally, it is doubtful whether the Popperian conception gives the possibility of a quantitative estimation of a hypothesis, since we can never point to all its potential falsifiers. Accepting the Popperian theory of probabilistic estimation, we would be compelled to state that the general theory of relativity hardly satisfied his methodological requirements, as we can point out few potential falsifiers, while the general field theory does not satisfy them at all. I am not convinced whether his and the Carnapian theories of the probabilistic estimation of scientific hypotheses are as opposed as Popper believes. It seems rather that both of them attempt to apply the calculus of probability for different aims, and are based on different interpretations of the calculus. The practical applicability of both conceptions in scientific research seems very limited.

    Google Scholar 

  13. The detailed analysis of these conventions may be found in I. Lakatos, ‘Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes’, in Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (ed. by I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave), Cambridge 1970, pp. 91–195.

    Google Scholar 

  14. I. Lakatos, ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  15. T. S. Kuhn, ‘Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research’, in Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge pp. 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  16. N. Bohr: ‘Discussions with A. Einstein on Epistemological Problems in Atomic Physics’, in Albert Einstein — Philosopher Scientist (ed. by P. Schilpp), Evanston 1959, pp. 199–243.

    Google Scholar 

  17. K. R. Popper, Conjectures and Refutations, pp. 215–248.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid., pp. 242–248.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid., pp. 231–234.

    Google Scholar 

  20. J. Agassi, ‘Science in Flux,’ Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science (ed. by R. S. Cohen and M. W. Wartofsky), Vol. III, Dordrecht 1967, pp. 293–324.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., p. 311.

    Google Scholar 

  22. K. R. Popper, Conjectures and Refutations, p. 248, footnote 31.

    Google Scholar 

  23. J. Agassi, ibid., p. 314.

    Google Scholar 

  24. In a footnote to the chapter ‘Unity of Method’ in Poverty of Historicism, Popper wrote (p. 131): “See my Logic of Scientific Discovery on which the present section is based, especially the doctrine of test by way of deduction (‘deductivism’) and of the redundancy of any further ‘induction’, since theories always retain their hypothetical character (‘hypotheticism’), and the doctrine that scientific tests are genuine attempts to falsify theories (‘eliminationism’)…”.

    Google Scholar 

  25. I. Lakatos, ‘Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes’ in Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, p. 106.

    Google Scholar 

  26. I. Lakatos, ibid., p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  27. K. Ajdukiewicz, ‘Das Weltbild und die Begriffsapparatur’, Erkenntnis 4 (1934) 262.

    Google Scholar 

  28. K. Ajdukiewicz, ‘W sprawie artykułu profesora A. Schaffa o moich poglądach filozoficznych’ (Reply to Professor A. Schaff’s Paper on my Philosophical Opinions), in K. Ajdukiewicz, Język i Poznanie (Language and Cognition), Vol. I, Warsaw 1965, p. 177.

    Google Scholar 

  29. A. Grünbaum, ‘Geometry, Chronometry and Empiricism’, in: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. III, 1062, pp. 405–527 (cf. especially pp. 419–424).

    Google Scholar 

  30. H. Poincaré, Science and Hypothesis, New York, 1952: “…no experiment will ever be in contradiction with Euclid’s postulate; but on the other hand, no experiment will ever be in contradiction with Lobatschewsky’s postulate” (p. 75) and “To sum up, whatever way we look at it, it is impossible to discover in geometric empiricism a rational meaning.” (p. 79) And further: “…this law [of inertia]…can be extended fearlessly to the most general cases; for we know that in these general cases it can neither be confirmed nor contradicted by experiment.” (p. 97)

    Google Scholar 

  31. W. V. Quine, ‘Carnap and Logical Truth’, in Logic and Language — Studies Deducated to Professor Rudolf Carnap, Dordrecht 1962, p. 63.

    Google Scholar 

  32. H. Poincaré, The Value of Science, New York 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  33. K. Ajdukiewicz, ‘Das Weltbild und die Begriffsapparatur’, p. 263.

    Google Scholar 

  34. K. R. Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery, p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1975 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Amsterdamski, S. (1975). Facts and Theories: Conventionalism. In: Between Experience and Metaphysics. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 35. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1797-8_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1797-8_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-277-0580-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-1797-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics