Skip to main content

‘Metaphysics’ — a Philosophical Discipline

  • Chapter
Hegel’s Dialectic

Part of the book series: Sovietica ((SOVA,volume 33))

  • 149 Accesses

Abstract

Andronicus of Rhodes (70 B.C.) gives to the sixth book of his collection of Aristotle’s works the title The Post-Physical’ (ta meta ta fysik?), since it follows the book of physics (fysike akroasi?). It is only since the late Middle Ages that all o? philosophy or one of its disciplines is designated by Andronicus’ term. Aristotle (384-322 B.C.) himself speaks of ‘wisdom’ (sofi?), ‘first philosophy’ (prote filosofik?) or ‘theology’ (theologik?). 1 For him, this science deals with being qu? being. He calls it ‘first philosophy’ because it investigates the eternal and firs? causes and principles of being,2 and he sometimes refers to it by the title ‘theology’ because he considers God as one of the first causes.3

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Cf. the analysis by Zimmermann.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Me. I Ac 1982 a 1-3.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Me. I A c 1 983 a 8-9.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Me. VIE c l 1026 a 13-16.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf. Heidegger 17; Owens 229; Moser 11; Zimmermann 101-108.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Metap., Proem; Moser 13ff.

    Google Scholar 

  7. De Tri. 5, 1, c: “… quia scientia de necessariis est … Omne quod necessarium inquantum huiusmodi est immobile.”

    Google Scholar 

  8. Eisler 128; Martin 203.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Wolff, G, Philosophia Rationali Frankfurt-Leipzig 1728, III, §99.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Descartes, R., Principia philosophia Amsterdam 1657, p. 7

    Google Scholar 

  11. Lo. I 35. Cf. Phä 35f. Cf. Martin 205.

    Google Scholar 

  12. K.r.. A 337, note.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Metaphysi 19. Cf. Eisler 129f.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Anfangsgründ 17.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Berl. Sch. 743ff.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Be. 91: “… for I identify logic with metaphysics…”

    Google Scholar 

  17. Be. 85f.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Lo. I 46f.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Lo. I 32f.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Lo. I 10, 16, 18f.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Interpreters have evaluated this identification in diverse ways. N. Hartmann regards it as compromising dialectic; Kroner (II 302f.), by contrast, as a revolution in the history of philosophy: “Hegel breaks with the view, sanctioned and fixed by a tradition of two thousand years, which alleges that logic is a science which can be taken out of the organism of philosophy… and be treated separately. With his innovation, he returns to Plato, for whom dialectic was a member of the whole of science.”

    Google Scholar 

  22. N.Hartmann III 17.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Lo. I 16.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Lo. I 31; Lo. II 356.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Lo. I 46. It should be noted that the content of imaginative representations (Vorstellungen) — including religious ones like ‘God’ — are thing-like and therefore subject to the same criticism as the world of things.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Be. 2; Re. I-I 7f. The relevance of formal logic for the study of religions has only recently be pointed out (Bochenski VI).

    Google Scholar 

  27. Bruaire29;J. Hoffmeister (Hegels Werk, Vol. XIX, Leipzig 1932,p. 115);G. Lasson (in Re. II-II, p. viii); Garaudy I 428; Kojève 538f.; Kruithof 76; Grégoire III 210. — Grégoire’s position is shared by Ballestrem. We cannot deal with this question in detail since we would have to take up too many questions which lie outside the realm of metaphysics of being (e.g., that of the relationship of faith and knowledge).

    Google Scholar 

  28. On the modern conception of formal logic, cf. Bocheński III, passi, esp. p. 326ff.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Cf. En. §§24, 42, 119 note, 162.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Cf. Part I, Chapter 3, notes 44ff.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Lo. I 33.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1975 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sarlemijn, A. (1975). ‘Metaphysics’ — a Philosophical Discipline. In: Hegel’s Dialectic. Sovietica, vol 33. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1736-7_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1736-7_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-1738-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-1736-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics