Skip to main content

Introduction

  • Chapter
Hegel’s Dialectic

Part of the book series: Sovietica ((SOVA,volume 33))

  • 147 Accesses

Abstract

This book is concerned with the essential features of Hegel’s dialectical method. It may be considered an introduction to the system of thought developed by the older Hegel, for this method pervades his entire system and coincides with th? form which is attributed to absolute spirit: For Hegel, everything which is (alles Seiend?) exists as a moment in a cycle pulsating with the force of contradiction.

In introductions, “that which in former ages occupied the mature minds of men [is supposed to have] sunk to the level of information, exercises, and even games, of boyhood”.

Hegel, Phenomenology of Spiri?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. En. §15. Cf. ibi § 17; Lo. I 56; Lo. II 500, 503f.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Jen. Lo. 140ff., 154f., 161ff., 168, 171, 175, 178, 181, 185; Realphi. 19, 29.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Cf. E. von Hartmann 119.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Marx 19.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Sartre 101: “SM’on se refuse a voirie mouvement dialectique originel dans l’individu et dans son entreprise de produire sa vie, de s’objectiver, il faudra renoncer à la dialectique ou en faire la loi immanents de l’Histoire.”

    Google Scholar 

  6. Lossky 70ff.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Feuerbach I 222f.: “Yet the secret of speculative philosoph [is] theology, speculative theolog which differs from ordinary theology in that it transfers the divine being which the latter, for fear and folly, removed into yonder world, into this world, i.e., it renders the divine being present, determinate, rea.” Cf. also Feuerbach II 426.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Lenin 321f.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Lenin 90, 172f., 197.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Lenin 182f., 250, 275.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf. Wetter I; and II 70, 116, 118,130.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. Bocheński I, and II 86-99, also IV 19-26.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Gfropp’s (151) accusation is directed against E. P. Sitkovskij in particular.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Efirov 26ff. — Equally characteristic of the Hegel interpretation in East-European philosophy are the publications by Gulian and Ovsjannikov. Gulian writes (II 725): “As has been noted, we discovered in the various parts of Hegel’s works a fickle relationship between these two aspects, a contradiction between method and system.” Ovsjannikov notes (284): “Hegel’s philosophy, as is clear from the entire preceding exposition, suffers from an internal contradiction. It includes in one unity opposing and, as it were, mutually exclusive aspects a revolutionary method and a conservative system.”

    Google Scholar 

  15. Cf. A. Hartmann.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Weisse II 36ff.; cf. also I 143ff.

    Google Scholar 

  17. I. H. Fichte I 308: “Not contradictio, but opposition that is infinitely overcome, the seeking and finding which complemen each other, lov, is the inner pulse of the world.” — I. H. Fichte II 29: Hegel’s view of the contradiction as determinately being “is his error, from which all the other errors can just as consistently be deduced in detail”.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Trendelenburg III 7; Haring 100.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Trendelenburg III 12ff.; cf. also 1125.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Überweg 204, 218.

    Google Scholar 

  21. E. von Hartmann 41.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Cf. Part I, Section 3.21, First Interpretation (C).

    Google Scholar 

  23. Cf. Michelet (Preface, p. viii).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Cf. Haring’s (98f.) criticism of Liebmann.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Haring 139. One could object to Haring that it is incorrect to represent dialectical-logical movement, movement of pure thought, by figures of circles. The same objection could be raised against our presentation, against Hegel’s expression ‘circle’ which appeals to the imagination, against drawings in mathematics and against mathematical-logical symbols. This objection can partly be invalidated by the advice that our figures be correctly interpreted: the elements of the dialectical movement which are dissociated in the figures must not be taken as spatially and temporally separate.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Albrecht 15ff. — A severe criticism of Coreth’s interpretation is to be found in Kruithof 290f. — N. Hartmann attempts to interpret and criticize Hegel using a notion of dialectic which is altogether unrelated to metaphysics and idealism (cf. our Part III, Section 2.33); according to Albrecht (9), Hegel’s method is inseparably conjoined with idealism, must rely on it as an “essential presupposition”, and loses all meaning when severed from it. According to ou interpretation, Hegel’s method presupposes extreme realism (in the sense explained in Part I, Chapter 1), and has idealism (the theory according to which the absolute is formed by a process of universals, in which there is no room for spatial and temporal separation) for its goal.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Haring 138.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Phalén l70.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Kroner 312; Kruithof 37.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Kruithof 25: “Many bookson Hegel… in Belgian and Dutch libraries are not cut open.” 31 Mure II (Introd., p. viii).

    Google Scholar 

  31. Kruithof 296.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Cf. Part I, Section 3.21, First Interpretation (B), (c).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Cf. Kruithof 19ff., 43f.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Hyppolite (II 234ff.) and Garaudy (I 200ff.) criticize the dualist interpretation of A. Kojève. They themselves (Hyppolite I 386; Garaudy I 213), however, fall into dualism when they claim, like dialectical materialists (cf. note 14), that there is an opposition between method and system. 36 Cf. Epilogue, note 13.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1975 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sarlemijn, A. (1975). Introduction. In: Hegel’s Dialectic. Sovietica, vol 33. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1736-7_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1736-7_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-1738-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-1736-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics