Advertisement

PSA 1974 pp 79-104 | Cite as

Galileo and Reasoning ex Suppositione: the Methodology of the two New Sciences

  • William A. Wallace
Part of the Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science book series (BSPS, volume 32)

Abstract

Galileo has been seen, from the philosophical point of view, alternately as a Platonist whose rationalist insights enabled him to read the book of nature because it was written in ‘the language of mathematics,’ and as an experimentalist who used the hypothetico-deductive methods of modern science to establish his new results empirically (McTighe, 1967; Settle, 1967; Drake, 1970; Shapere, 1974). Both of these views present difficulties. In this paper I shall make use of recent historical research to argue that neither is correct, that the method utilized by Galileo was neither Platonist nor hypothetico-deductivist, but was basically Aristotelian and Archimedean in character. This method, moreover, was not merely that of classical antiquity, but it had been emended and rejuvenated in the sixteenth century, and then not by Greek humanist Aristotelians or by Latin Averroists but rather by scholastic authors of the Collegio Romano whose own inspiration derived mainly from Thomas Aquinas. Other influences, of course, were present, and these came from other medieval and Renaissance writers, but these need not concern us in what follows.

Keywords

Middle Period Heavy Body Lunar Eclipse Hypothetical Reasoning Movable Object 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Bibliography

  1. Blake, R. M, Ducasse, C. J., and Madden, E. H.: 1960, Theories of Scientific Method: The Renaissance through the Nineteenth Century, Univ. of Washington Press, Seattle.Google Scholar
  2. Crombie, A. C: 1975, ‘The Sources of Galileo’s Early Natural Philosophy’, in M. L. Righini Bonelli and W. R. Shea (eds.), Reason, Experiment, and Mysticism in the Scientific Revolution, Science History Publications, New York, 1975, pp. 157–175, 303-305.Google Scholar
  3. Drake, S.: 1970, Galileo Studies: Personality, Tradition, and Revolution, Univ. of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor.Google Scholar
  4. Drake, S.: 1973a, ‘Galileo’s Discovery of the Law of Free Fall,’ Scientific American 228, pp. 84–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Drake, S.: 1973b, ‘Galileo’s Experimental Confirmation of Horizontal Inertia: Unpublished Manuscripts’, (Galileo Gleanings XXII), Isis 64, pp. 290–305.Google Scholar
  6. Drake, S. (ed.): 1974, Galileo Galilei: Two New Sciences, including Centers of Gravity and Force of Percussion, translated with introduction and notes, Univ. of Wisconsin Press, Madison.Google Scholar
  7. Duhem, P.: 1913, Etudes sur Léonard de Vinci,Vol. 3, A. Hermann et Fils, Paris.Google Scholar
  8. Duhem, P.: 1969, To Save the Phenomena. An Essay on the Idea of Physical Theory from Plato to Galileo, tr. E. Doland and C. Maschler, Univ. of Chicago Press, Chicago and London.Google Scholar
  9. Favaro, A. (ed.): 1890–1909, Le Opère di Galileo Galilei, 20 vols, in 21, G. Barbèra, Florence, reprinted 1968.Google Scholar
  10. Finnochiaro, M. A.: 1972, ‘Vires acquirit eundo: The Passage Where Galileo Renounces Space-Acceleration and Causal Investigation’, Physis 14, 125–145.Google Scholar
  11. Fredette, R.: 1972, ‘Galileo’s De motu antiquiora\ Physis 14, 321–348.Google Scholar
  12. Harré, R.: 1972, The Philosophies of Science. An Introductory Survey. Oxford Univ. Press, London, Oxford and New York.Google Scholar
  13. Koertge, N.: 1974, ‘Galileo and the Problem of Accidents’, paper read to the British Society for the Philosophy of Science, October 7, 1974, being readied for publication.Google Scholar
  14. Koyré, A.: 1939, Etudes Galiléenes, Hermann, Paris, reprinted 1966.Google Scholar
  15. Koyré, A.: 1968, Metaphysics and Measurement. Essays in Scientific Revolution, Harvard Univ. Press, Cambridge, Mass.Google Scholar
  16. Koyré, A. and Cohen, I. B.: 1972, Isaac Newton’s Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathe-matica, 3d ed. of 1726 with variant readings, 2 vols., Harvard Univ. Press, Cambridge, Mass.Google Scholar
  17. MacLachlan, J.: 1973, ‘A Test of an “Imaginary” Experiment of Galileo’s,’ Isis 64, 374–379.Google Scholar
  18. McTighe, T. P.: 1967, ‘Galileo’s “Platonism”: A Reconsideration’, in E. McMullin (ed.), Galileo, Man of Science, Basic Books, Inc., New York and London, 1967, pp. 365–387.Google Scholar
  19. Naylor, R. H.: 1974, ‘Galileo and the Problem of Free Fall’, The British Journal for the History of Science 7, 105–134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Purnell, F.: 1972, ‘Jacopo Mazzoni and Galileo’, Physis 14, 273–294.Google Scholar
  21. Schmitt, C. B.: 1972, ‘The Faculty of Arts at Pisa at the Time of Galileo’, Physis 14, 243–272.Google Scholar
  22. Settle, T. B.: 1961, ‘An Experiment in the History of Science’, Science 133, 19–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Settle, T. B.: 1967, ‘Galileo’s Use of Experiment as a Tool of Investigation’, in E. McMullin (ed.), Galileo, Man of Science, Basic Books, Inc., New York and London, 1967, pp. 315–337.Google Scholar
  24. Shapere, D.: 1974, Galileo: A Philosophical Study, Univ. of Chicago Press, Chicago and London.Google Scholar
  25. Shea, W. R.: 1972, Galileo’s Intellectual Revolution. Middle Period 1610–1632, Science History Publications, New York.Google Scholar
  26. Shea, W. R. and Wolf, N. S.: 1975, ‘Stillman Drake and the Archimedean Grandfather of Experimental Science’, to appear in Isis.Google Scholar
  27. Wallace, W. A.: 1959, The Scientific Methodology of Theodoric of Freiberg, Fribourg Univ. Press, Fribourg.Google Scholar
  28. Wallace, W. A.: 1968, ‘The Enigma of Domingo de Soto: Uniformiter difformis and Falling Bodies in Late Medieval Physics’, Isis 59, 384–401.Google Scholar
  29. Wallace, W. A.: 1969, ‘The “Calculatores” in Early Sixteenth-Century Physics’, The British Journal for the History of Science 4, 221–232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Wallace, W. A.: 1971, ‘Mechanics from Bradwardine to Galileo’, Journal of the History of Ideas 32, 15–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Wallace, W. A.: 1972, Causality and Scientific Explanation, Vol. I. Medieval and Early Classical Science, Univ. of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor.Google Scholar
  32. Wallace, W. A.: 1974a, Causality and Scientific Explanation, Vol. II. Classical and Contemporary Science, Univ. of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor.Google Scholar
  33. Wallace, W. A.: 1974b, ‘Galileo and the Thomists’, St. Thomas Aquinas Commemorative Studies 1274-1974, 2 vols., Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, Toronto, 1974, Vol. 2, pp. 293–330.Google Scholar
  34. Wallace, W. A.: 1974c, ‘Theodoric of Freiberg: On the Rainbow’, in A Source Book in Medieval Science, E. Grant (ed.), Harvard Univ. Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1974, pp. 435–441.Google Scholar
  35. Wallace, W. A.: 1974d, ‘Three Classics of Science: Galileo, Two New Sciences, etc.’, in The Great Ideas Today 1974, Encyclopaedia Britannica, Chicago, pp. 211–272.Google Scholar
  36. Wisan, W. L.: 1974, ‘The New Science of Motion: A Study of Galileo’s De motu locali, Archive for History of Exact Sciences 13, 103–306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland 1976

Authors and Affiliations

  • William A. Wallace
    • 1
  1. 1.The Catholic University of AmericaUSA

Personalised recommendations