Advertisement

PSA 1974 pp 423-434 | Cite as

The Conventionality of Slow-Transport Synchrony

  • Peter A. Bowman
Part of the Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science book series (BSPS, volume 32)

Abstract

The conventionality of distant simultaneity, as maintained by Hans Reichenbach and Adolf Grünbaum, is by now so widely known that it can be stated very briefly. Let us consider two points A and B which are separated from one another in an inertial frame K. For a light signal emitted from A and reflected at B back to A, we compare the time interval for the out-going trip to that for the round trip. This ratio is called ‘epsilon’ (≤). In formulating the special theory of relativity, Einstein effectively took ≤ to be ½ thus, we may use ≤=½ in defining what is now called ‘standard signal synchrony’. Reichenbach views ⊀ as being restricted only by the causal relations involved in the signaling process. That is, the reflection of the light ray at B must take place after the ray’s emission at A but before its return to A. These considerations require us to restrict ∈ between zero and one, but Reichenbach (1958, p. 127) insists that within these limits values of ∈≠ ½ “could not be called false”. He claims that there are no facts which would mediate against using these values in definitions which are now called ‘nonstandard signal synchrony’. This allegedly physical possibility of choosing ∈ between zero and one is the conventionality of distant simultaneity as determined by signals. Grünbaum (1973, p. 353) also argues for this thesis, making clear that it obtains within a single inertial frame.1 In this paper I will not be concerned with the situation in more than one inertial frame.2 Rather, I will consider a nonsignaling definition of synchrony and ask what sort of conventionality it manifests in a single inertial frame.

Keywords

Special Relativity Inertial Frame Causal Explanation Relative Speed Electron Theory 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Bibliography

  1. Bowman, P. A.: 1972, ‘Conventionality in Distant Simultaneity: Its History and Its Philosophy’, Ph.D. dissertation, Indiana University.Google Scholar
  2. Bowman, P. A.: 1976, ‘On Conventionality and Simultaneity — Another Reply’, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. VIII (ed. by J.Earman and C.Glymour), forthcomGoogle Scholar
  3. Bowman, P. A.: 1976a, ‘The Rejection of Newtonian Simultaneity by Lorentz and Larmor’, forthcoming.Google Scholar
  4. Bowman, P. A.: 1976b, ‘Henri Poincaré and the Light Principle’, forthcoming.Google Scholar
  5. Bridgman, P. W.: 1962, A Sophisticate’s Primer of Relativity, Wesleyan Univ. Press, Middletown, Conn.Google Scholar
  6. Earman, J. and Friedman, M.: 1973, ‘The Meaning and Status of Newton’s Law of Inertia and the Nature of Gravitational Forces’, Philosophy of Science 40, 329–359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Ellis, B. D.: 1963, ‘Universal and Differential Forces’, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 14, 177–194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Ellis, B. D.: 1965, ‘The Origin and Nature of Newton’s Laws of Motion’, in R. G. Colodny (ed.), Beyond the Edge of Certainty, Univ. of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh.Google Scholar
  9. Ellis, B. D.: 1966, Basic Concepts of Measurement, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
  10. Ellis, B. D.: 1971, ‘On Conventionality and Simultaneity — A Reply’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49, 177–203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Ellis, B. D. and Bowman, P. A.: 1967, ‘Conventionality in Distant Simultaneity’, Philosophy of Science 34, 116–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Grünbaum, A.: 1969, ‘Simultaneity by Slow Clock Transport in the Special Theory of Relativity’, Philosophy of Science 36, 5–43; reprinted in Grünbaum (1973, pp. 670-708).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Grünbaum, A.: 1970, ‘Space, Time and Falsifiability: Introduction and Part A’, Philosophy of Science 37, 469–588; reprinted in Grünbaum (1973, pp. 449-568).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Grünbaum, A.: 1973, Philosophical Problems of Space and Time, 2nd ed. (Synthese Library), D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht and Boston; 1st ed. published 1963.Google Scholar
  15. Hunt, I. E. and Suchting, W. A.: 1969, ‘Force and “Natural” Motion’, Philosophy of Science 36, 233–251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Lorentz, H. A.: 1937, ‘Versuch einer Theorie der elektrischen und optischen Erscheinungen in bewegten Körper’, in Collected Papers, Vol. V (ed. by P. Zeeman and A. D. Fokker), Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague.Google Scholar
  17. Poincaré, H.: 1954, Oeuvres de Henri Poincaré, Vol. IX, Gauthier-Villars, Paris.Google Scholar
  18. Reichenbach, H.: 1958, The Philosophy of Space and Time (translated by M. Reichenbach and J. Freund), Dover Publications, New York; German ed. published 1928.Google Scholar
  19. Reichenbach, H.: 1969, Axiomatization of the Theory of Relativity (translated by M. Reichenbach), University of California Press, Berkeley and Los Angeles; German ed. published 1924.Google Scholar
  20. Schaffner, K. F.: 1969, ‘The Lorentz Electron Theory [and]_Relativity’, American Journal of Physics 37, 498–513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Winnie, J.: 1970, ‘Special Relativity Without One-Way Velocity Assumptions: Parts I and II’, Philosophy of Science 37, 81–99 and 223-238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland 1976

Authors and Affiliations

  • Peter A. Bowman
    • 1
  1. 1.The University of TennesseeKnoxvilleUSA

Personalised recommendations