Skip to main content

Memory. Reproduction and Association

  • Chapter
Knowledge and Error

Part of the book series: Vienna Circle Collection ((VICC,volume 3))

  • 196 Accesses

Abstract

On a walk through the streets I meet a man whose face, frame, gait and speech provoke in me a lively idea of such a set of charateristics in different surroundings. I recognize X who stands before me as a sense experience to be the same as forms a part of my memories from the other setting. Recognition and identification would be senseless unless X were given twice over. Soon I recall previous conversations with him in the other surroundings, joint excursions and so on. Similar situations are observed in the most varied circumstances, and we may gather them under a rule: a sense experience, consisting of ABCD, revives the memory of an earlier one consisting of AKLM, thus reproducing it as an idea. Since KLM is not generally reproduced by BCD, we naturally take it that the common element A starts the process. First A is reproduced, and then follow KLM which were directly experienced with it or with other simultaneous features already reproduced. All processes in this field can be subsumed under this one law of association.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Experience has taught us to recognize stabilities; our mental organisation easily adapts itself to them and affords us advantages. Next, we consciously and arbitrarily introduce the presupposition of further stabilities expecting further benefits if the presupposition proves itself. The assumption of a concept given a priori as foundation of this methodological procedure we neither need nor would derive any advantage from. It would be a mistake in view of the obviously empirical formation of this concept.

    Google Scholar 

  2. C. L. Morgan, Comparative Psychology, London 1894, pp. 85 f.

    Google Scholar 

  3. This however is also the behaviour of decorticated birds. The phenomenon thus would seem to rest on an ancestrally acquired reflex; cf. the end of this chapter.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Schneider, Der tierische Wille, Leipzig 1880.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Observation by my daughter.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Next to the writings of Morgan, the following are instructive as to the psychology of lower and higher animals: K. Möbius, Die Bewegungen der Tiere und ihr psychischer Horizont (Monographs of the Naturwissensch. Verein f. Schleswig-Holstein 1873); A. Oelzelt-Newin, Kleinere philosophische Schriften. Zur Psychologie der Seesterne, Vienna 1903. Amongst older books I should recommend H. S. Reimarus, Triebe der Tiere 1790, and J. F. H. Autenrieth, Ansichten über Natur- und Seelenleben 1836.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Wundt, Philosophische Studien X, p. 323.

    Google Scholar 

  8. That not all mental processes are explicable in terms of temporally acquired conscious associations will be discussed later. Here we are concerned with what is intelligible by means of association.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. James, The Principles of Psychology I, pp. 550–604.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Well-known cases of this sort are the following: Voltaire dreams a complete variant canto of the ‘Henriade’. Stranger still is Tartini’s dream of the devil playing him a movement of a sonata that the violinist had been unable to achieve when awake, unless the report be a compromise between fiction and truth.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Jerusalem, Lehrbuch der Psychologie, 3rd. ed. Vienna 1902, p. 91.

    Google Scholar 

  12. These questions will be discussed more fully later.

    Google Scholar 

  13. One might be tempted to regard ‘active’ thinking as essentially different from ‘passive’ idling of thoughts. Yet just as we have no control over sense impressions and memories triggered off by a bodily action, so we have none over a notion of direct or indirect biological interest which always recurs and connects with new series of associations. Cf. P 3, pp. 287–308.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Hobbes, Physica IV, 25.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Anyone who thinks he can build up the world out of consciousness cannot have clearly grasped how complicated is the fact of consciousness. Succinct accounts eminently worth reading on the nature and conditions of consciousness are to be found in Wernicke, Gesammelte Aufsätze, Berlin 1893, pp. 130–145. Cf. also the lectures of Meynert cited below.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Meynert, Populäre Vorträge, Vienna 1892, pp. 2–40.

    Google Scholar 

  17. We can hardly doubt that the different parts of the brain perform differently. If nevertheless, as shown by Goltz, one part of the cortex can gradually function as substitute for another, we cannot think in terms of abrupt limits to functions but only of a gradual localisation in the sense of R. Semon (Die Mneme, Leipzig 1904, p. 160). Cf. also A 4, p. 155.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Kussmaul, Störungen der Sprache, Leipzig 1885.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid., p. 175.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid., p. 182.

    Google Scholar 

  21. On Remarkable disturbances in musicians resembling aphasia and agraphia see R. Wallaschek, Psychologie und Pathologie der Vorstellung, Leipzig J. A. Barth 1905.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Wilbrand, Seelenblindheit, Wiesbaden 1887, pp. 43–51.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid., p. 57.

    Google Scholar 

  25. A. Forel, Der Hypnotismus, 6th ed., pp. 236f. contains the description of a most peculiar case of amnesia.

    Google Scholar 

  26. In the light of such periodic disturbances of memory, observations like those of Swoboda (Die Perioden des menschlichen Organismus, 1904) seem not at all so extraordinary as they might look at first glance.

    Google Scholar 

  27. C. Detto, ‘Über den Begriff des Gedächtnisses in seiner Beleuchtung für die Biologie’, Naturwiss. Wochenschr. 1905, No. 42. The author will hardly suppose that Hering or Semon would fall into the errors he criticizes. However, I think he underrates the advantage of examining the organic from two sides. Psychological observation can reveal the existence of physical processes that we should not so readily come to know by way of physics.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1976 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mach, E., Hiebert, E.N. (1976). Memory. Reproduction and Association. In: Knowledge and Error. Vienna Circle Collection, vol 3. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1428-1_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1428-1_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-277-0282-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-1428-1

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics