Skip to main content

Economics and Ethics II

Substantive Ethics

  • Chapter
Book cover Principles of Ethical Economy

Part of the book series: Issues in Business Ethics ((IBET,volume 17))

  • 170 Accesses

Abstract

The rationality of formal ethics and economics follows two principles: the individual maximization of the attainment of subjectively-defined goals and the coordination of maximization. Coordination takes place as ethical coordination within the decision-maker by means of universalization, and as economic coordination externally by the decision-maker and the price system. The formation of preferences is directed toward universalization; the economic coordination of preferences is directed toward the ability of persons to live together. In the formal ethics of rules, as in the economic coordination of the price system, the content of the ethical will is formed by rules. Can the ethical side of the determination of the will, which should be achieved by ethics, consist only in the formal principle of universalization? If ethics is determined only by the categorical imperative, is it not underdetermined, because it should not merely clarify the question of how I can best achieve what I already intend here and now — as economics does — and because it should not merely answer the question of what I should do — as Kantian ethics does? Ethics must instead also provide an answer to the question of what I should or can desire, if I have become conscious of my will by taking distance and expanding the perspective of my self and the situation in which I stand. Ethics must seek to explain what asuccessful life is on the whole, not merely which actions are universalizable. Ethics serves to answer the question of what I actually do and can desire.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Literatur

  1. Cited by Hans Albert, Marktsoziologie und Entscheidungslogik (Neuwied. 1967). p. 42.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Cf. Max Scheler, Der Formalismus in der Ethik und die materiale Wertethik, 6th Ed. (Bern. 1980), pp. 122–26, 493–94, III.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Marcus Tullius Cicero, De Invent. Rhet. II. 52, as cited by Thomas Aquinas. Summa Theologiae, II-II, q. 145, a. I.

    Google Scholar 

  4. 4 Scheler, Der Formalismus in der Ethik und die materiale Wertethik, pp. 114–16.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf. Wilhelm Korff, „Ethische Entscheidungskonflikte,“ in Handbuch der christlichen Ethik (Freiburg and Gütersloh, 1982), Vol. Ill, p. 79.

    Google Scholar 

  6. 6 Wilhelm Dilthey, Der Aujbau der geschichtlichen Welt in den Geisteswissenschaften (Frankfurt, 1981), pp. 235 ff. See also Eduard Spranger, “Wilhelm Dilthey.” in Spranger. Vom pädagogischen Genius (Heidelberg, 1965), pp. 209–10.

    Google Scholar 

  7. 7 Eduard Spranger, „Vom Wesen des Geistigen,“ in Gesammelte Schriften, ed. Hans Walter Bähr (Tübingen, 1980), Vol. VI, p. 307. Earlier, Heinrich Rickert, Science and History. trans. George Reisman (Princeton, 1962), p. 65: “The science of psychology aspires to explain the nature of psychical existence by seeking to discover its general laws or any other general concepts. But the ‚psychological ‘knowledge of mental life that we seek to acquire in the study of history consists in re-experiencing it in its individual course.”

    Google Scholar 

  8. Cf. Spranger, „Vom Wesen des Geistigen,“ p. 311.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. Wilhelm Wundt, System der Philosophie (Leipzig, 1889), Vol. I, p. 337.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Cf. Spranger, Das Gesetz der ungewollten Nebenwirkungen in der Erziehung, 6th Ed. (Heidelberg, 1960), p. 101. See also Otto Bollnow, Existenzphilosophie und Pädagogik, 5th Ed. (Stuttgart, 1977), pp. 105 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf. Spranger, Ibid., pp. 94–95.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. G. L. S. Shackle, Imagination and the Nature of Choice (Edinburgh, 1979), pp. 2 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  13. On the theory of “public goods,” see Richard A. Musgrave and Peggy B. Musgrave. Public Finance in Theory and Practice, 2nd Ed. (Englewood Cliffs, N. J, 1976), pp. 49 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  14. The phenomenon of cohesion and separation through the pursuit of different goods has already been seen by means of the example of Augustine. The genus of private (earthly) goods excludes others, according to him, since with the genus of the goods of this world is necessarily tied to “competition of consumption.” Therefore, there will always be envy and strife in the state. It is otherwise, according to Augustine, with the good of the civitas Dei, of the love of God. Possession of it does not create strife, but community and unity: “Unlike material possessions, goodness is not diminished when it is shared, either momentarily or permanently, with others, but expands and, in fact, the more heartily each of the lovers of goodness enjoys the possession the more does goodness grow …, it is [a possession] that increases the more its possessor loves to share it” (The City of God, trans. G. G. Walsh and G. Monahan (Washington, 1952), Book XV, Chap. 5, p. 421). The amor sui creates strife and division, but the amor Dei creates community and unity, because no one can have possession of the love of God “who is unwilling to share it” (Ibid.). The City of God, trans. G. G. Walsh and G. Monahan (Washington, 1952), Book XV, Chap. 5, p. 421) The amor Dei has eminently political significance as the principle of reconciliation and political cohesion.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Terence Irwin (Indianapolis, 1985), III, 8, 1114 b 27: “Certain actions produce [the virtues], and they cause us to do these same actions, expressing the virtues themselves.”

    Google Scholar 

  16. Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, trans. George Long (London, 1862), XI, 18.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, Theodicy, trans. E. M. Huggard. 1952, § 208, p. 257.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See also Serge-Christophe Kolm, “Must One Be Buddhist to Grow?” in Koslowski. ed. Economics and Philosophy (Tübingen, 1985), pp. 225–28, on the relationship between the principle of “the end in the means” in Buddhist ethics and Japanese economic growth.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Friedrich Schleiermacher, Grundlinien einer Kritik der bisherigen Sittenlehre (Berlin, 1803), pp. 176–77: “So Kant has both duties that are virtue-duties and duties that are not virtueduties, but are nevertheless ethical duties; then also various duties whose performance is virtuous. but not virtue-dutiful. And one minute he writes that one can say that we are obligated to virtue. then the next minute he writes that one cannot say that it is obligatory to possess the virtues.”

    Google Scholar 

  20. Cf. below, Section 8.2.4., pp. 197-202.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cf. Josef Pieper. “Justice,” trans. Lawrence E. Lynch, in The Four Cardinal Virtues (Notre Dame, Ind., 1966), pp. 70–75.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, V, 1, 1129 a 8–9.

    Google Scholar 

  23. For an investigation of the specific justice of exchange and distribution, and the general justice as virtue simply, see Aristotle, Ibid., V, 2, 1129 b 25 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Plato, Republic, trans. Paul Shorey, in The Collected Dialogues, ed. Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns (New York, 1961), IV, 441 c ff.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Plato, Cratylus, trans. Benjamin Jowett, in The Collected Dialogues, 412 e.

    Google Scholar 

  26. The Greeks, in the words of Werner Jaeger, Paideia, trans. Gilbert Highet (New York. 1939), Vol I., p. 158, saw “creation to be a cosmos ‘writ large’ — namely a community of things under law.”

    Google Scholar 

  27. Cf. Heraclitus: “The sun will not overstep his bounds; if he does, the Erinnyes, allies of justice, will find him out,” Fragment 29, in Milton C. Nahm, ed., Selections from Early Greek Philosophy, 3rd Ed. (New York, 1947), p. 90.

    Google Scholar 

  28. According to J. and W. Grimm, Deutsches Worterbuch (Munich, 1984), the meaning of the German adjective passend (fitting, appropriate, suitable) is central to the meaning of the German adjective gerecht (just).

    Google Scholar 

  29. 30 Schleiermacher, Grundlinien einer Kritik der bisherigen Sittenlehre, p. 87.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Schleiennacher, Grundlinien einer Kritik der bisherigen Sittenlehre, p. 247.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Cf. Koslowski, „Maximierung von Existenz,“ Studia Leibnitiana. 19 (1987), pp. 54–67.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, I, 7, 1098 a 10: “Now we take the human function to be a certain kind of life, and take this life to be the soul’s activity and actions that express reason. The excellent man’s function is to do this finely and well. Each function is completed well when its completion expresses the proper virtue. Therefore, the human good turns out to be the soul’s activity that expresses virtue. And if there are more virtues than one, the good will express the best and most complete virtue. Moreover, it will be in a complete life.”

    Google Scholar 

  33. Cf. James M. Buchanan, “Economics and Its Scientific Neighbors,” in Buchanan, What Should Economists Do? Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1979, p. 118. With Buchanan, to be sure. this position has the features of a thought experiment.

    Google Scholar 

  34. G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica (Cambridge, 1903), p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Cf. Koslowski, Ethik des Kapitalismus, 6th Ed. (Tübingen, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  36. Immanuel Kant, Foundations ofthe Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Lewis White Beck (New York, 1959), p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, I–II, q. 18, a. 4, ad. 3, with reference to Pseudo-Dionysius, De divinis nominibus, c. 4: “Evil results from any single defect, but good from the complete cause.” Cf. Peter Lombard, Libri Quatuor Sententiarum, 1158, II, d. 36. See also [Cursus] Collegii Salmanticensis, Cursus Theologicus, tract. XI, disp. IV, dub. I (Comm. in S. Thomae s. th. I–II, q. 18, a. 3): Because each substance becomes perfect in the physical order by those accidentals, so also each moral act becomes perfect in its order by whatever circumstances and receives from them the completion of its morality, whether goodness or evilness.” Leibniz also defines the good as the possible perfection of a thing or action. Kant (Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, pp. 61-62), objects, incorrectly, that the concept of perfection is empty. Even if there is no universally and categorically applicable rule of perfection, it does not follow that the concept of perfection is empty. It is a concept at the limit, whose function is orientation.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Koslowski, P. (2001). Economics and Ethics II. In: Principles of Ethical Economy. Issues in Business Ethics, vol 17. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0956-0_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0956-0_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4020-0364-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-0956-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics