Skip to main content

Violence and the Socratic Theory of Legal Fidelity

  • Chapter
Retribution, Justice, and Therapy

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series in Philosophy ((PSSP,volume 16))

Abstract

We are inclined to think of Socrates as a rebel against the society of his day. We also think of him as a man whose intellectual rebellion took a negative form — i.e., instead of propounding philosophical theories of his own, he revealed his wisdom in destroying through rational criticism the theoretical pretensions of his fellow citizens. Given these expectations, the dialogue Crito contains substantial surprises. For, though containing negative criticisms of Crito’s arguments, it is in the main an elaborate theoretical defense of obedience to the political powers that be. A part of this theoretical defense consists of a statement of a political theory, the social contract theory, which — at least until the time of Hegel and Marx — was the most influential theory in political thinking about such matters as obedience to law and political violence. For it is primarily a theory of legal fidelity — i.e., a theory which attempts to establish a moral obligation to obey the law, a moral obligation to honor one’s legal obligations. This theory has strongly affected philosophical thinking about violence because, according to most social contract theory, the greatest criticism to be made against violence is that it is illegal. Indeed, some of these theorists (e.g., Hobbes and Kant) are inclined to define violence as the illegal use of force or coercion. This assimilation of the problem of violence to the problem of disobedience, and the related tendency to regard law as the central concept of politics, are both present in the Crito.1

In the following essay, I have for the most part death with Apology and Crito (relying on the translations by Benjamin Jowett and F. J. Church) as though they are philosophical works in English. I do not think this is totally unjustified because (a) the issues raised in the translations are of intrinsic philosophical interest and (b) it is primarily in translation that these works have had an impact in the recent history of ideas. Where some issue of translation did seem important, I was able to obtain assistance, for which I am very grateful, from my colleague Ronald Milo. I also found it useful to consult W. D. Adkins’ Merit and Responsibility, A Study in Greek Values (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1960).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. This assimilation of the problem of violence to the problem of disobedience to law still crops up in some surprising places. See for example, Robert Paul Wolffs essay ‘On Violence’, Journal of Philosophy LXVI (Oct. 2, 1969) 601–16, where what starts to be a discussion of violence very quickly shifts into a discussion of civil disobedience. In my reply to Wolff (‘Violence and the Rule of Law’, Ethics 80 [July 1970], 319–21) I was guilty of the same assimilative tendency.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. ‘Socrates on Disobeying the Law’, The Philosophy of Socrates, ed. Gregory Vlastos (Garden City: Anchor Books, 1971), pp. 299–318. I have had the opportunity of discussing this article, in conjunction with an early draft of my own present essay, with Professor Woozley. I have learned much from these discussions though not, I suspect, as much as I should have.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Private and subjective appeals on matters of this nature did not by any means end with Socrates but are still represented, for example, in attempts to justify civil disobedience by appeals to the “voice of conscience.” The appeals made in Thoreau’s famous ‘On the Duty of Civil Disobedience’ are roughly of this sort and are, in my judgment, to be rejected for lacking what Kant would call universalizability.

    Google Scholar 

  4. The Greek adjective generally translated as harmful, injurious, or evil is kakon, and the Greek verbs for harming or causing injury are blapto and kakourgeo. We must suppose that Socrates is persuasively defining these terms to make any sense at all of his famous claim (Apology, 41) that “no evil or harm can happen to a good man.” For good men can surely be treated unjustly and made to suffer pain and death. What a good or just man cannot be, however, is bad or unjust. Thus only if being harmed is being unjust can it be true (though tautologically true, of course) that a good man cannot be harmed. This notion of harm runs throughout much of Plato’s writings. See, for example, Republic, 335, where Socrates argues that to harm a man is to injure him and that to injure a man is to make him unjust. The term “persuasive definition” was coined by C. L. Stevenson in his article of that title in Mind (1938). One persuasively defines a term when, for evaluative purposes, one attempts to alter its normal usage (e.g. extend it to a new class of things) while preserving its emotive overtones. For the use of such definitions in Greek ethics, see W. D. Adkins, Merit and Responsibility, A Study in Greek Values (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1960). On 265 he discusses the Socratic claim (at Crito, 47) that committing injustice is harmful, kakon, to the man who commits it.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Op. cit., 308.

    Google Scholar 

  6. The notion that injustice deteriorates or maims the soul is explicitly expressed at Crito, 47.

    Google Scholar 

  7. This necessity for supplementing Socrates’ argument with a principle of fairness is stressed in Woozley, op. cit., 315 ff. The principle I have given above would obviously need refinement (e.g., specification of the act description A, elaboration of relevant circumstances, etc.) before it would be acceptable, but that would be an object for another paper.

    Google Scholar 

  8. ‘Legal Obligation and the Duty of Fair Play’, Law and Philosophy, ed. S. Hook (New York: New York University Press, 1964), reprinted in my Civil Disobedience and Violence (Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1971). See, for a further elaboration of his social contract theory, his ‘Justice as Fairness’, The Philosophical Review, 67 (1958) 164–194.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See also my ‘In Defense of Obligation’ in Nomos XII: Political and Legal Obligation, ed. J. Roland Pennock and John W. Chapman (New York: Atherton Press 1970), pp. 36–45.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See on this point Ronald Dworkin’s ‘On Not Prosecuting Civil Disobedience’, in my Civil Disobedience and Violence (Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1971). See also my ‘The Vietnam War and the Right of Resistance’ in the same volume.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Chapter VII, The Concept of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1961).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1979 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Murphy, J.G. (1979). Violence and the Socratic Theory of Legal Fidelity. In: Retribution, Justice, and Therapy. Philosophical Studies Series in Philosophy, vol 16. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-9461-4_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-9461-4_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-277-0999-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-9461-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics