Skip to main content

Abstract

The aim of the present chapter is to consider some basic elements of Hegel’ views on economic matters in the light of the Scottish influence on him. Before beginning the account of a market economy which Hegel gives in his “System of Needs”, it is necessary to bring to mind that he had previously provided — in his section on ‘Abstract Right’ (§§34–104) — some of the very presuppositions which Smith’s and Steuart’s models of economic life required for their proper functioning, most notably, private property, the existence of money as a general means of exchange, and an elaborate system of private law, centring on the law of contract. These presuppositions, though not always explicitly re-stated, are supposed to be effictive throughout the “System of Needs”. Like-wise, these pre-conditions of the ‘system of needs’ are later comple-mented in his ‘Rechtspflege’ (‘The Administration of Law’ ; §§ 209–229, an account of the means by which abstract right is enforced. A detailed consideration of these features goes beyond the scope of the present work,2 but it will be shown briefly that the institutional, jurisprudential framework of Hegel’s economic model already betrays significant par-allels with the Scots’ views.

In political economy [Volkswirtschaft] everything is done out of personal interest, but nature arranges it in such a manner that it serves ethical purposes. [...] Ethical life is the higher reason which, as Hegel expresses it, possesses enough cunning to create an ethical purpose behind the backs of men, a purpose which they neither anticipated nor intended. C.L. Michelet (1866).1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Carl Ludwig Michelet, Naturrecht und Rechtsphilosophie als die praktische Philosophie enthaltend Rechts-, Sitten- und Gesellschaftslehre. In 2 vols. (Berlin, 1866) Vol. I, pp. 6 f.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See: Joachim Ritter, “Person und Eigentum”, and Peter Landau, “Hegels Begründung des Vertragsrechts”, both in Manfred Riedel (1975) Vol. II, pp. 152–175 and 176–197 respectively.

    Google Scholar 

  3. VRP, Vol. II, § 46, p. 216 - TMK, p. 42: “Since my will, as the will of a person, and so as a single will, becomes objective to me in property, property acquires the character of private property.”

    Google Scholar 

  4. This difference has recently been clarified by Christopher Berry, “Property and Possession: Two Replies to Locke — Hume and Hegel”, J.R. Pennock & J.W. Chapman (Eds.), Property (New York, 1980) pp. 89–100; a comparison which throws light on both accounts.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cp.: Landau/Riedel (1975) Vol. II, pp. 180 f.

    Google Scholar 

  6. VRP, Vol. II, § 71, p. 296 - TMK, p. 57: “Contract presupposes that the parties entering it recognize each other as persons and property owners. It is a relationship at the level of mind objective, and so contains and presupposes from the start the moment of recognition.”

    Google Scholar 

  7. VRP, Vol. II, § 63, p. 260 - TMK, p. 51; for Aristotle’s own exposition see: Nicomachean Ethics Book V.8. I have used the German edition: Die Nikomachische Ethik. Translated and edited by Olof Gigon (Zürich, 2nd edition, 1967) pp. 163–166.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Peter Landau, I think, makes this point in too sweeping a manner: Landau/Riedel (1975) Vol. II, p. 182.

    Google Scholar 

  9. VRP, Vol. II, pp. 261 f; cp.: Hegel’s early distinction between ‘ideal’ and ‘empirical measure’ of goods (SdS, p. 437).

    Google Scholar 

  10. A gulf, incidentally, which supports our previous claim that Hegel’s direct knowledge of Ricardo was rather limited.

    Google Scholar 

  11. A point which Paul Chamley (1969, p. 157) has rightly stressed.

    Google Scholar 

  12. This definition is illustrated with the example of “silver-plate curiously wrought” of which “the intrinsic worth subsists entire” (SJS, Vol. I, p. 312).

    Google Scholar 

  13. SJS, Vol. II, p. 409: “The value of things depends upon many circumstances, which however may be reduced to four principal heads: First, The abundance of the things to be valued. Secondly, The demand which mankind make for them. Thirdly, The competition between the demanders; and Fourthly, The extent of the faculties of the demanders.”

    Google Scholar 

  14. SdS, pp. 32 + 66; HGW, Vol. VI, p. 324; HGW, Vol. VIII, p. 225.

    Google Scholar 

  15. VRP, Vol. II, note to § 63, p. 263; cp.: VRP, Vol. III, pp. 240 f; VRP, Vol. IV, p. 229; and Hegel’s aphorism of the Berlin period: “Money is the abbreviation of all external need” (TWA, Vol. XI, p. 565).

    Google Scholar 

  16. SJSW, Vol. I, p. 42: “By Money, I understand any commodity, which purely in itself is of no material use to man for the purposes above-mentioned, but which acquires such an estimation from his opinion of it, as to become the universal measure of what is called value, and an adequate equivalent for any thing alienable.” See also: SJSW, Vol. II, pp. 270–278.

    Google Scholar 

  17. This point has been stressed by George E. Davie, “Anglophobe and Anglophil”, SJPE, Vol. XIV (1967) pp. 291–302, here p. 296.

    Google Scholar 

  18. SJS, Vol. I, p. 20: “Man we find acting uniformly in all ages, in all countries, and in all climates, from the principles of self-interest...”

    Google Scholar 

  19. For Smith, there is not only the famous passage in the “Wealth of Nations”, on the butcher, brewer, and baker whose self-interest makes them provide our dinner (SGE, Vol. II. 1, pp. 26 f), but also a number of passages from the “TMS”: SGE, Vol. I, pp. 85 f, 135, 173.

    Google Scholar 

  20. VRP, Vol. I, p. 308- Cp.: VRP, Vol. II, § 182, p. 633-TMK, p. 122: “The concrete person, who is himself the object of his particular aims...”; VRP, Vol. II, § 187, p. 636 -TMK, p. 124; TWA, Vol. VII, Addition to § 182+, p. 339- TMK, p. 267:“In civil society each member is his own end, everything else is nothing to him.”

    Google Scholar 

  21. VRP, Vol. III, p. 472: “The particular interest of individuals”.

    Google Scholar 

  22. VRP, Vol. II, § 183, p. 633-TMK, p. 123: “selfish ends”; cp.: VRP, Vol. III, p. 569; VRP, Vol. IV, p. 473.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Immanuel Kant, “Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Purpose”, Hans Reiss (Ed.), Kant’s Political Writings (Cambridge, 1970) p. 44.

    Google Scholar 

  24. My own translation of: VRP, Vol. I, p. 308.

    Google Scholar 

  25. VRP, Vol. II, § 196, p. 644 - TMK, p. 128.

    Google Scholar 

  26. TWA, Vol. VII, § 189+, p. 347: “dieses Wimmeln von Willkür — TMK,” p. 268: “this medley of arbitrariness”. Cp.: VRP, Vol. III, p. 576 & Vol. IV, pp. 486, 491 f.

    Google Scholar 

  27. The whole purpose of AF1 could be described as a ‘natural history of man’ and Ferguson is highly explicit about this methodological feature (AF1, pp. 4 f); see also AF2, pp. 15–75, and compare Smith’s ‘Lectures on Jurisprudence’ (SGE, Vol. V, pp. 333 ff & 487 ff).

    Google Scholar 

  28. Adam Ferguson, Grundsatze der Moralphilosphie. Uebersetzt und mit Anmerkungen versehen von Christian Garve (Leipzig, 1772) pp. 300 f.

    Google Scholar 

  29. SGE, Vol. II, 1, p. 181: “... the desire of the conveniences and ornaments of building, dress, equipage, and household furniture, seems to have no limit or certain boundary... those desires as opposed to the desire of food... cannot be satisfied, but seem to be altogether endless.”

    Google Scholar 

  30. SJS, Vol. I, p. 139: “there are no bounds to the consumption of work...”

    Google Scholar 

  31. VRP, Vol. III, p. 576. In his “Theory of Moral Sentiments” Smith actually uses the very formulation “insatiable desires” (SGE, vol. I, p. 184).

    Google Scholar 

  32. Marginal note to Hotho’s lecture notes; according to Ilting, this note was dictated by Hegel’s assistant, Leopold von Henning (VRP, Vol. III, p. 574 and cp.: pp. 81 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Especially Smith: SGE, Vol. V, pp. 333 f & 487 f.

    Google Scholar 

  34. VRP, Vol. II, § 190, p. 641 - TMK, p. 127: “... by the differentiation and division of concrete need into single parts and aspects which in turn become different needs, particularized and so more abstract.” Cp.: VRP, Vol. III, pp. 590 f, Vol. IV, p. 489.

    Google Scholar 

  35. VRP, Vol. III, pp. 591 ff (my own italics; N.W.); cp.: HGW, Vol. VIII, p. 243; VRP, Vol. I, p. 311 & Vol. II, § 191, p. 542 - TMK, p. 127 & Vol. III, p. 588 (L.v. Henning). -Man’s refinement of desires and corresponding skills is equally stressed by Smith and Ferguson: AF1, pp. 6 f & 168; SGE, Vol. II, 1, p. 181 & Vol. V, p. 335.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Compare the growing literature on Hegel’s concept of labour: Ivan Dubsky, Hegels Arbeitsbegriff und die idealistische Dialektik (Prag, 1961);

    Google Scholar 

  37. Bernhard Lakebrink, “Geist und Arbeit im Denken Hegels”, Philosophisches, Jahrbuch Vol. 70 (1962/63) pp. 98–108;

    Google Scholar 

  38. Sok-Zin Lim, Der Begriff der Arbeit bei Hegel. Versuch einer Interpretation der Phänomenologie des Geistes (Bonn, 2nd ed. 1966).

    Google Scholar 

  39. TWA, Vol. VII, § 191 +, p. 349 - TMK, p. 269; cp.: VRP, Vol. III, p. 593. — Adam Smith does indeed use the word “comfortably” in a passage which distinguishes ‘necessaries’ from ‘luxuries’ (SGE, Vol. II.2, pp. 869 f).

    Google Scholar 

  40. Paul Chamley (1963) tentatively suggested this parallel (pp. 88 f), but as the Berlin lectures were not available to him, his case was less convincing.

    Google Scholar 

  41. AF2, p. 66; cp.: AF1, p. 7: Even “naked in the woods” man finds a “badge of superiority” in “the strength of his limbs and the sagacity of his mind”; Hume, “Essays”, p. 309, note 1.

    Google Scholar 

  42. AF2, p. 31: “Men, in all ages, are fond of decoration.”

    Google Scholar 

  43. SGE, Vol. II.2, pp. 869 f: “By necessaries I understand, not only the commodities which are indispensably necessary for the support of life, but whatever the custom of the country renders it indecent for creditable people, even of the lowest order, to be without.”

    Google Scholar 

  44. AF1, p. 7: “The occupations of men, in every condition, bespeak their freedom of choice, their various opinions, and the multiplicity of wants by which they are urged...”

    Google Scholar 

  45. As opposed to his implicit use of the concept of ‘labour’ in his discussion of property.

    Google Scholar 

  46. VRP, Vol. IV, p. 496 (my own italics; N.W.) - cp.: VRP, Vol. II, § 196, p. 644-TMK, p. 128.

    Google Scholar 

  47. TMK, § 196, p. 128; cp.: VRP, Vol. III, p. 601.

    Google Scholar 

  48. For the wider implications of ‘Bildung’ in the ‘Phenomenology’, compare: I. Dubsky (1961); B. Lakebrink (1962/63); S.-Z. Lim (1966).

    Google Scholar 

  49. TMK, § 197, p. 129; cp.: VRP, Vol. III, pp. 605 f & Vol. IV, p. 500.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Paul Chamley, “La Doctrine Economique De Hegel Et La Conception Hégélienne Du Travail”, HSBh 4 (Bonn, 1969) pp. 147–159.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Cp.: P. Chamley (1969) p. 155: “Il est donc faux de dire que, dans la doctrine économique hégélienne, le travail joue a lui seul, par lui-même, un rôle mediateur. C’est là le rôle du travail et de l’échange, du travail pour l’échange.”

    Google Scholar 

  52. SJS, Vol. I, p. 17; cp.: ibid., p. 89: “... the best way of binding a free society together is by multiplying reciprocal obligations, and creating a general dependence between all its members.” (my own italics in both quotations; N.W.).

    Google Scholar 

  53. Helmut Reichelt’s introduction to his edition of: G.W.F. Hegel, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts (Frankfurt, 1972) p. xxxvi.

    Google Scholar 

  54. A criticism frequently directed against Adam Smith as well as Hegel. With regard to Smith, this criticism can be found in: G. Myrdal, Das politische Element in der nationalökonomischen Doktrinbildung (Hannover, 2nd edition, 1963) pp. 158 f; Lucio Coletti, “Mandeville, Rousseau è Smith”, Ideologia è Societa (Bari, 3rd edition, 1972) pp. 288 ff. Helmut Reichelt (1972) may serve as an example of the application of this criticism to Hegel.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Karl-Heinz Ilting and others have rightly stressed that the systematic shape of Hegel’s early economic views, as contained in the “System der Sittlichkeit” (1802/3), follows the first book of Aristotle’s “Politics”; cp.: K.-H. Ilting, “Hegels Auseinandersetzung mit der aristotelischen Politik”, Philosophisches Jahrbuch. Vol. 71 (München, 1963/64) pp. 38–58. However, the Aristotelian frame soon proved inadequate for the integration of the modern materials, as derived from the Scottish economists, and thus sank to the position of a dwindling influence.

    Google Scholar 

  56. TMK, § 299, p. 195; see also TMK, §§ 185, 206, 262+; pp. 123 f, 133, 280 & VRP, Vol. III, pp. 634 f & 722; Vol. IV, pp. 523 & 637. A worthwhile, though partly dated, treatment of Hegel’s criticism of Plato is to be found in M.B. Foster, The Political Philosophies of Plato and Hegel (Oxford, 1935) Chapter III, pp. 72–98; appendix E, pp. 101–109.

    Google Scholar 

  57. In this context, Hutcheson appeals to pity, “the sentiments of compassion and humanity,... even tho’ it [slavery] could be vindicated by some plea of external right [this is alluding to the case of captives].” Francis Hutcheson, A System of Moral Philosphy (London, 1755) Vol. II, p. 203 - Cp.: Wylie Sypher, “Hutcheson and the ‘Classical’ Theory of Slavery”, Journal of Negro History (1939) Vol. XXIV, pp. 263–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  58. In this context, Hutcheson refers to “the natural rights of mankind” and appeals to his readers’ “sense of natural justice”: Hutcheson (1755) Vol. II, pp. 201 & 85. - Cp.: T.D. Campbell, “Francis Hutcheson: ‘Father’ of the Scottish Enlightenment”, R.H. Campbell & A.S. Skinner (Eds.), The Origins and Nature of the Scottish Englightenment (Edinburgh, 1982) pp. 167–185, here pp. 177 f.

    Google Scholar 

  59. AF1, p. 185: “We feel its injustice [of slavery]; we suffer for the helot, under the severities and unequal treatment to which he was exposed...” & AF2, p. 201: “No contract or forfeiture can deprive a man of all his rights, or render him the property of another. No one is born a slave; because every one is born with all his original rights.”

    Google Scholar 

  60. Duncan Forbes, “Natural Law and the Scottish Enlightenment”, R.H. Campbell & A.S. Skinner (1982) pp. 186–204, here p. 193.

    Google Scholar 

  61. For contemporary critical reaction, see: The Critical Review. Vol. 23 (1767) p. 413 & The Monthly Review. Vol. 36 (1767) p. 465. Both reviews disapproved of Steuart’s example of slavery: Lycurgus’ Sparta, an example which will soon be commented upon in greater detail. — Johannes Hoffmeister, in his notes to DHE (P. 467), misrepresents Steuart’s position as recommending slavery (“empfiehlt.. direkte Sklavenhalterei”).

    Google Scholar 

  62. SJS, Vol. I, pp. 168 f: “Where hands therefore are principally necessary, the slaves have the advantage; where heads are principally necessary, the advantage is in favour of the free.”

    Google Scholar 

  63. David Hume, The History of England. In 8 vols. (Oxford, 1826) Vol. I, chapter 3, Appendix, Section 5: “The Several Orders of Men”, pp. 186–189.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Cp.: Duncan Forbes, Hume’s Philosophical Politics (Cambridge, 1975) p. 311.

    Google Scholar 

  65. SGE, Vol. II.2, p. 681; cp.: SGE, Vol. V, p. 192 and Vol. II. 1, p. 80: “.. . Indostan or antient Egypt (where every man was bound by a principle of religion to follow the occupation of his father, and was supposed to commit the most horrid sacrilege if he changed it for another)... (my own italics; N.W.) — Hegel also refers to “a religious authority” (TMK, § 206, p. 133).

    Google Scholar 

  66. Compare VRP, Vol. II, § 299, p. 766 - TMK, p. 195 with SGE, Vol. II.2, p. 681.

    Google Scholar 

  67. SJS, Vol. II, p. 381: “We see by the works of Xenophon, of Plato, of Aristotle, and of many other writers of merit, that, in their age, all professions which were calculated to gain money, were regarded as unworthy of a freeman ... Plato would have a citizen punished who should enter commerce.” Cp.: SGE, Vol. II.1, p. 388.

    Google Scholar 

  68. This has convincingly been demonstrated by H.F. Fulda, Das Recht der Philosophie in Hegels Philosophie des Rechts (Franfurt, 1968), pp. 48 f.

    Google Scholar 

  69. DHW, Vol. III, p. 291: “It is well known with what peculiar laws Sparta was governed, and what a prodigy that republic is justly esteemed by every one, who has considered human nature as it has displayed itself in other nations, and other ages. Were the testimony of history less positive and circumstantial, such a government would appear a mere philosophical whim or fiction, and impossible ever to be reduced to practice.” (my own italics; N.W.)

    Google Scholar 

  70. SJS, Vol. I, p. 218: “Of this plan [of Lycurgus’ republic] we have a description in the life of this legislator written by Plutarch ...” — AF1, pp. 62, 157, 196, 229.

    Google Scholar 

  71. SJS, Vol. I, p. 220: “Whatever regards any other object than his plan of political economy, shall here be passed over in silence.”

    Google Scholar 

  72. S.R. Sen came to a similar conclusion: The Economics of Sir James Steuart (London, 1957) p. 133.

    Google Scholar 

  73. SJS, Vol. I, pp. 220–223; compare those aspects with Hegel’s fullest treatment of Sparta, in the “Lectures on the Philosophy of World History”, TWA, Vol. XII, pp. 319–323.

    Google Scholar 

  74. These fragments were first edited by Karl Rosenkranz (1844) pp. 520 f & 525 and are now conveniently to be found in DHE, pp. 263 f, 268 f and TWA, Vol. I, p. 434.

    Google Scholar 

  75. According to Rosenkranz, they belong to Hegel’s Bern period, but Hoffmeister, Lukács and others consider them to be from the Frankfurt years.

    Google Scholar 

  76. See above, p. 164; cp.: Sen (1957) p. 131.

    Google Scholar 

  77. DHE, p. 268 (my own italics; N.W.) — TWA, Vol. I, p. 439; cp.: SJS, Vol. I, pp. 169 & 221.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Wilhelm Seeberger, Hegel oder die Entwicklung des Geistes zur Freiheit (Stuttgart, 1961).

    Google Scholar 

  79. Cp.: SJS, Vol. I, p. 217: “When once a state begins to subsist by the consequences of industry, there is less danger to be apprehended from the power of the sovereign.” — AF1,

    Google Scholar 

  80. pp. 143 f; 261: “It has been found, that, except in a few singular cases, the commercial and political arts have advanced together.”

    Google Scholar 

  81. AF1, p. 160; cp.: SJS, Vol. I, pp. 218 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  82. AF1, p. 263; cp.: SJS, Vol. I, pp. 70 f.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Hume (1826) Vol. III, pp. 262–270 “Remarks on the Progress of Science and Government.”

    Google Scholar 

  84. William Robertson, The History of the Reign of the Emperor Charles V. [1769], here quoted from The Works of William Robertson. In 12 vols. (London, 1824) Vol. IV, pp. 196–210, 233–240.

    Google Scholar 

  85. The German ‘Die ‘Stande’ implies both ‘social classes’ and ‘estates’ (in their political function), see: VRP, Vol. II, § 303, p. 773 - TMK, p. 197 f. Since, in what follows, I am mainly dealing with the social dimension, I have used the rendering ‘classes’ throughout the present section.

    Google Scholar 

  86. See: Franz Rosenzweig (1920) Vol. I, p. 138; Vol. II, p. 122; and the more recent study by R.K. Hocevar, Hegel und der Preussische Staat (München, 1973) pp. 86–90. The implied irrelevance of Hegel’s discussion is perhaps the main reason why this aspect of Hegel’s thought has received comparatively little attention.

    Google Scholar 

  87. It is disputed, however, whether one should identify the traditional nobility or Napoleon’s ennobled military officers with this level of Hegel’s account; cp.: Haym (1857) p. 177; Rosenzweig (1920) Vol. I, p. 135; Lukács (1973) Vol. II, p. 584.

    Google Scholar 

  88. SdS, pp. 472 f- SoEL, p. 153: “The former utility is that the first class is the absolute and real ethical shape and so, for the other classes, the model of the self-moving and self-existent Absolute, the supreme real intuition which ethical nature demands.”

    Google Scholar 

  89. SdS, p. 473 - SoEL, p. 153: “The latter utility, according with the mode of the other classes, lies in the negative [i.e. in labour], and on the part of the first class labour is established likewise, but it is the absolutely indifferent labour of government and courage.”

    Google Scholar 

  90. SdS, p. 475 - SoEL, p. 155: “The greatest height which this class can attain by its productive activity is (a) its contribution to the needs of the first class and (b) aid to the needy.”

    Google Scholar 

  91. SdS, p. 473 - SoEL, p. 153.

    Google Scholar 

  92. SdS, p. 476 - SoEL, p. 156.

    Google Scholar 

  93. ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  94. HGW, Vol. VIII, p. 269

    Google Scholar 

  95. Rosenzweig thus seems to over-emphasize the difference when he contrasts Hegel’s views of 1802, characterized by feudalism and estates [‘aristokratisch-ständisch’], with a later level of ‘monarchisch-bürokratisch’ (1920) Vol. I, p. 189.

    Google Scholar 

  96. TWA, Vol. III, pp. 435 & 513; TWA, Vol. IV, p. 63.

    Google Scholar 

  97. SJS, Vol. I, p. 301: “There must be a third class; to wit, those who are maintained and taken care of at the expense of the whole community, in order to serve as a defence.”

    Google Scholar 

  98. SJS, Vol. I, p. 57 — It ought to be remembered that ‘industry’ is a technical term for Steuart (SJS, Vol. I, p. 146).

    Google Scholar 

  99. G.E. Davie (SJPE, 1967) p. 292 — My argument is indebted to Dr. Davie’s interpretation of Steuart’s ‘middlemen’.

    Google Scholar 

  100. SJS, Vol. I, p. 149: “... the better to simplify our ideas, we supposed the transition to be direct from the manufacturer to the consumer, and both to be members of the same society.” (my own italics; N.W.)

    Google Scholar 

  101. SJS, Vol. I, p. 16: “The statesman (this is a general term to signify the legislature and supreme power, according to the form of government) ...”

    Google Scholar 

  102. SJSW, Vol. V, p. 227; cp.: SJS, Vol. I, pp. 142–145.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1988 Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Waszek, N. (1988). Hegel’s Account of the Market Economy. In: The Scottish Enlightenment and Hegel’s Account of ‘Civil Society’. Archives Internationales D’Histoire des Idées / International Archives of the History of Ideas, vol 120. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2750-6_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2750-6_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7735-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2750-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics