Advertisement

Abstract

It has become conventional to introduce a study in the history of ideas by giving some indication of the wider relevance of the ideas and thinkers that are being dealt with. The addition of another book to the thousands of studies on Hegel — in the present case a lengthy investigation of one, at first glance, rather obscure source of Hegel’s philosophy, i.e. the Scottish Enlightenment — seems to require special justification. A common way of providing such justification is to stress the vital rôle of the figure under investigation in the history of thought, i.e. to refer to his established place in a ‘sacred’ mausoleum, and then to define the aspect on which the respective study is trying ‘to throw new light’, i.e. to locate one’s own efforts in the front court of the mausoleum. This indirect method of justifying one’s research is perfectly legitimate and, in the case of Hegel, perfectly easy, for very few philosophers would nowadays dare to treat him like a ‘toter Hund’.

Keywords

Eighteenth Century Planetary Motion Scottish Journal Scottish School Newtonian Science 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 1.
    Michael Theunissen, Hegels Lehre vom absoluten Geist als theologisch-politischer Traktat (Berlin, 1970) p. viii — Cp.: Joachim Ritter, “Vorbemerkung”, J. Ritter & R. Heede (Eds.), Hegel-Bilanz (Frankfurt, 1973) p. ix.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    See below, pp. 15–17; 21–30.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    H.G. Gadamer, Das Erbe Hegels, Rede aus Anlaβ der Verleihung des Hegel-Preises 1979 der Stadt Stuttgart (Frankfurt, 1979) p. 35.Google Scholar
  4. 6.
    Iring Fetscher, “Reflexionen uber Zynismus als Krankheit unserer Zeit”, Alexander Schwan (Ed.), Denken im Schatten des Nihilismus. Festschrift für Wilhelm Weischedel (Darmstadt, 1975) pp. 334–345.Google Scholar
  5. 7.
    HGW, Vol. IX, p. 322 — In Hegel, of course, this term is applied to ‘la terreur’.Google Scholar
  6. 8.
    F. Heer, “Hegel und die Jugend”, G.K. Kaltenbrunner (Ed.), Hegel und die Folgen (Freiburg, 1970) pp. 19–36, here pp. 22f.Google Scholar
  7. 9.
    Otto Pöggeler, “Werk und Wirkung”, O. Pöggeler (Ed.), Hegel (Freiburg & München, 1977) p. 21.Google Scholar
  8. 10.
    Hegel, “Antrittsvorlesung Berlin 1818”, HBS, p. 8.Google Scholar
  9. 11.
    HBr, Vol. IV.2, Letter 27a, p. 4, dated August 7, 1798.Google Scholar
  10. 12.
    Hegel, “Letter to Schelling, dated November 2, 1800”, HBr, Vol. I, Letter 29, p. 59.Google Scholar
  11. 13.
    Cp.: Hegel, “Letter to Schelling, dated April 16, 1975”, HBr. Vol. I, Letter 11, p. 24-HL, p. 35.Google Scholar
  12. 14.
    Otto Poggeler, Hegels Idee einer Phänomenologie des Geistes (Freiburg & München, 1973) p. 123, cp. alsop. 161.Google Scholar
  13. 15.
    An example of such invectives is: Willy Hochkeppel, “Dialektik als Mystik”, G.K. Kaltenbrunner (Ed.), Hegel und die Folgen (Freiburg, 1970) pp. 69–112Google Scholar
  14. 15a.
    for a much better attempt to define Hegel’s relationship to Mysticism, see: Theodor Steinbüchel, “Hegel und Meister Eckhart”, Universitas Vol. II (1947) pp. 1409–1423.Google Scholar
  15. 16.
    Michael Theunissen (1977; p. 3) describes this ‘unholy alliance’ of Hegel opponents in similar terms.Google Scholar
  16. 17.
    Cp.: Duncan Forbes, “Introduction”, G.W.F. Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of World History. Translated by H.B. Nisbet (Cambridge, 1975) p. XII — Henceforth quoted as “HBN”, Roman page numbers are to Duncan Forbes’s introduction.Google Scholar
  17. 18.
    Ernst Bloch, Subjekt-Objekt. Erläuterungen zu Hegel (Frankfurt, 3rd edition, 1972) p. 18.Google Scholar
  18. 19.
    Cp.: Christoph Helferich, Hegel (Stuttgart, 1979) p. 196: “Thus, it is the ‘relation ship’ between Hegel and Marx that still remains, whether openly expressed or otherwise, the secret focal point of discussion and will remain so in the future, as long as the desires of both — a reconciled whole — cannot or does not wish to be realized.”Google Scholar
  19. 20.
    Herbert Marcuse, Reason and Revolution. Hegel and the Rise of Social Theory (New York, 1941).Google Scholar
  20. 21.
    Eduard Gans, “Vorwort zur 2. Ausgabe der Rechtsphilosophie” (1833), now in: Manfred Riedel, Materialien zu Hegels Rechtsphilosophie (Frankfurt, 1975) Vo. I, pp. 242–248, here p. 243.Google Scholar
  21. 22.
    Riedel (1975) p. 36.Google Scholar
  22. 23.
    HBN, pp. XXXIII f.Google Scholar
  23. 24.
    Ernst Bloch, Naturrecht und menschliche Würde (Frankfurt, 1961).Google Scholar
  24. 25.
    Jürgen von Kempski, “Bloch, Recht und Marxismus”, J.v. Kempski, Brechungen. Kritische Versuche zur Philosophie der Gegenwart (Hamburg, 1964) pp. 176–180, here pp. 176 & 178.Google Scholar
  25. 26.
    Otto Poggeler, “Diskussionsbeitrag zu Iring Fetschers Referat”, Hegel-Bilanz, op. cit., p. 214.Google Scholar
  26. 28.
    Iring Fetscher, “Diskussionsbeitrag”, Hegel-Bilanz, op. cit., p. 215.Google Scholar
  27. 29.
    Cp. my article: “Die Hegeische Schule”, in: Pıpers Handbuch der politischen Ideen, in 5 vols., edited by Iring Fetscher und H. Munkler (München, will appear in 1986).Google Scholar
  28. 30.
    R. Heede, “Hegels Religionsphilosophie als Aufgabe und Problem der Forschung”, Hegel-Bilanz, op. cit., p. 84.Google Scholar
  29. 31.
    Heinz Kimmerle, “Zu Hegels Religionsphilosophie”, Philosophische Rundschau, Vol. 15 (1968) p. 126.Google Scholar
  30. 32.
    Cp.: HBN, p. XXVI: “It is a blasphemy for a Christian to think of God as in any way unknown, a concealed object acting on mankind from without in a manner humanly unknown and unknowable.”Google Scholar
  31. 33.
    Karlfried Gründer, “Diskussionsbeitrag zu Karl Löwiths Referat”, Hegel-Bilanz, op. cit., p. 30.Google Scholar
  32. 34.
    W.D. Marsch, Gegenwart Christi in der Gesellschaft. Eine Studie zu Hegels Dialektik (München, 1965)Google Scholar
  33. 34a.
    Falk Wagner, Der Gedanke der Persönlichkeit Gottes bei Fichte und Hegel (Gütersloh, 1971)Google Scholar
  34. 34b.
    Peter Cornehl, Die Zukunft der Versohnung. Eschatologie und Emanzipation in der Aufklarung, bei Hegel und in der Hegeischen Schule (Göttingen, 1971)Google Scholar
  35. 34c.
    W. Pannenberg, “Die Bedeutung des Christentums in der Philosophie Hegels”, Stuttgarter Hegel Tage 1970, HSBh (1974) pp. 175–202, Jörg Splett, Die Trinitätslehre G.W. F. Hegels (München, 1965)Google Scholar
  36. 34d.
    Heinrich Beck, Der Akt-Charakter des Seins (München, 1965)Google Scholar
  37. 34e.
    Hans Kung, Menschwerdung Gottes. Eine Einführung in Hegels theologisches Denken als Prolegomena zu einer künftigen Christologie (Basel, Freiburg, Wien, 1970)Google Scholar
  38. 34f.
    Q. Lauer, Hegel’s Concept of God (Albany, 1982).Google Scholar
  39. 35.
    C. Bruaire, Logique et religion chretienne dans la philosophie de Hegel (Paris, 1965)Google Scholar
  40. 35a.
    A. Chapelle, Hegel et la religion. In 2 vols. (Paris, 1964–1971); M. Theunissen, op. cit.; E.L. Fackenheim, The Religious Dimension in Hegel’s Thought (London-Bloomington, 1967)Google Scholar
  41. 35b.
    A. Léonhard, La foi chez Hegel (Paris, 1965).Google Scholar
  42. 36.
    Hegel himself refers to this passage: TWA, Vol. XVI, p. 43.Google Scholar
  43. 37.
    Theunissen, op. cit., p. 51.Google Scholar
  44. 38.
    M.J. Petry in the introduction to his edition of Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature. In 3 vols. (London, 1970) Vol. I, p. 21Google Scholar
  45. 39.
    Henning Ottmann, Individuum und Gemeinschaft bei Hegel. Vol. I: Hegel im Spiegelder Interpretationen (Berlin & New York, 1977) p. 11CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. 40.
    I have used this anecdote, for which there may be other sources, as it is related by Marx: H.M. Enzensberger (Ed.), Gesprache mit Marx und Engels (Frankfurt, 1973) Vol. I, pp. 315 f.Google Scholar
  47. 41.
    Eduard Gans, “Nekrolog’”, Allgemeine Preussische Staatszeitung. December 1, 1831. Now in: Günther Nicolin (Ed.), Hegel in Berichten seiner Zeitgenossen (Hamburg, 1970) pp. 490–496, here p. 496 — Henceforth quoted as “HBZ”.Google Scholar
  48. 42.
    Karl Rosenkranz, Geschichte der Kantischen Philosophie (Leipzig, 1840).Google Scholar
  49. 43.
    Duncan Forbes, “Review of Judith N. Shklar’s ‘Freedom and Independence’”, Clio (Fort Wayne, 1978) Vol. VII, No. 3 pp. 514–516, here p. 514Google Scholar
  50. 44.
    Karl Rosenkranz, G.W.F. Hegels Leben (Berlin, 1844) p. XXVIIIGoogle Scholar
  51. 45.
    Karl Rosenkranz, Kritische Erläuterungen des Hegeischen Systems (Konigsberg, 1840) p. XXXVGoogle Scholar
  52. 46.
    For example: Theodor Haering, Hegel. Sein Wollen und sein Werk. In 2 vols. (Leipzig, 1929 & 1938)Google Scholar
  53. 46a.
    Herbert Marcuse, Reason and Revolution (New York, 1941)Google Scholar
  54. 46b.
    Georg Lukács, Der junge Hegel und die Probleme der kapitalistischen Gesellschaft (Zurich, 1948)Google Scholar
  55. 46c.
    Ernst Bloch, Subjekt — Objekt (Leipzig, 1951).Google Scholar
  56. 47.
    Charles Taylor, Hegel (Cambridge, 1975); cp. my review of the recent German translation of Taylor’s study in Hegel-Studien Vol. XVII (1982) pp. 226–229. — Henceforth quoted as “HS”.Google Scholar
  57. 48.
    Heinz Kimmerle, “Religion und Philosophie als Abschluss des Systems”, Otto Pöggeler, Hegel (Freiburg & München, 1977) p. 154, has a nice compilation of such topics.Google Scholar
  58. 49.
    Karl Lowith, “Aktualitat und Inaktualitat Hegels”, Hegel-Bilanz, op. cit., p. 16Google Scholar
  59. 50.
    Otto Poggeler, “Perspektiven der Hegel-Forschung”, Hegel-Studien: Beiheft XI (Bonn, 1970) pp. 79–102. — Henceforth quoted as “HSBh”.Google Scholar
  60. 51.
    ibid., p. 101Google Scholar
  61. 52.
    Their books and articles are too numerous to list here, cp.: Kurt Steinhauer (Ed.), Hegel- Eıne internationale Bibliographie (München, 1980).Google Scholar
  62. 53.
    For a survey of previous research, see below.Google Scholar
  63. 54.
    H.S. Harris, Hegel’s Development. Toward the Sunlight 1770–1801 (Oxford, 1972) p. XVIIGoogle Scholar
  64. 55.
    “Differenzschriff”, HGW, Vol. IV, pp. 1–93 and HSH, passim.Google Scholar
  65. 56.
    For an introduction to the various sets of lecture notes and their usage in various editions of the History of Philosophy, cp. TWA, Vol. XX, pp. 520–527 and below, p. 134Google Scholar
  66. 57.
    G.W.F. Hegel, Enzyklopaedie der philosophischen Wissenschaften. Vorrede zur dritten Ausgabe (1830), TWA, Vol. VIII, p. 36Google Scholar
  67. 58.
    G.W.F. Hegel, Vorlesungen uber die Geschıchte der Phılosophıe, TWA, Vol XX, p. 310.Google Scholar
  68. 59.
    Richard Kroner, Von Kant bis Hegel. In 2 vols. (Tubingen, 1921 & 1924).Google Scholar
  69. 60.
    F.W.J. Schelling, Philosophie der Mythologie. In 2 vols. (1856) = Reprint: (Darm stadt, 1976) Vol. I, p. 583Google Scholar
  70. 61.
    Rudolf Haym, Hegel und seine Zeıt (Berlin, 1857) = Reprint (Darmstadt, 1962) p. 28Google Scholar
  71. 62.
    Dilthey’s approach to Hegel was first articulated in his review of Karl Hegel’s edition of Hegel’s letters: Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, (1888) pp. 289–299; also: Wilhelm Dilthey, Die Jugendgeschichte Hegels (1905), now in Gesammelte Schriften Vol. IV (Göttingen & Stuttgart, fifth edition, 1974) pp. 1–187.Google Scholar
  72. 63.
    Cp.: José M. Ripalda, The Divided Nation (Assen/Amsterdam, 1977) p. 9: “Dilthey saw the Enlightenment as little more than the precursor of Romanticism and of the bourgeois society of the 19th century. The Enlightenment, the time of small books, and names without the aura of genius, could attract only with difficulty the congenial sympathy of a sensitive soul in search of its own images.”Google Scholar
  73. 64.
    Wilhelm Dilthey, op. cit., pp. 138 ff.Google Scholar
  74. 65.
    H. Nohl, Hegels theologische Jugendschriften (Tübingen, 1907). Henceforth quoted as “HTJ”.Google Scholar
  75. 66.
    Georg Lukács, Der junge Hegel (1948), here quoted from the edition: (Frankfurt, 1973), Vol. I, p. 15.Google Scholar
  76. 67.
    Annemarie Gethmann-Siefert, “Hegel Archiv und Hegel Ausgabe”, Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, Vol. 30, Part 4 (1976) p. 609; Otto Pöggeler, “Perspektiven der Hegelforschung”, op. cit., pp. 88 f.Google Scholar
  77. 68.
    Hermann Nohl, op. cit.; Georg Lasson (Ed.), Hegel: Schriften zur Politik und Rechtsphilosophie (Leipzig, 2nd edition, 1923)Google Scholar
  78. 68a.
    Georg Lasson (Ed.), Hegel: Erste Druckschriften (Leipzig, 1928)Google Scholar
  79. 68b.
    Georg Mollat (Ed.), Hegel: Die Verfassung des Deutschen Reiches (Stuttgart, 1935).Google Scholar
  80. 69.
    Johannes Hoffmeister (Ed.), Dokumente zu Hegels Entwicklung (Stuttgart, 1936). Henceforth quoted as “DHE”.Google Scholar
  81. 71.
    Cp.: Joachim Ritter, Hegel und die französische Revolution [1957], I have used the following edition: (Frankfurt, 1972) p. 52.Google Scholar
  82. 72.
    Justus Schwarz, “Dokumente zu Hegels Frühzeit. Bemerkungen anläβlich der Veröffentlichung der Dokumente zu Hegels Entwicklung durch J. Hoffmeister”, Blätter für Deutsche Philosophie, Vol. XII (1938/39) pp. 416–423Google Scholar
  83. 72a.
    Justus Schwarz, Hegels philoso phische Entwicklung (Frankfurt, 1938).Google Scholar
  84. 73.
    For a bibliography of these authors, see the appendix to: H.R. Rottleuthner, “Die Substantialisierung des Formalrechts”, Oskar Negt (Ed.), Aktualität und Folgen der Philosophie Hegels (Frankfurt, 1970) pp. 215–268; for a critical discussion, besides Rottleuthner see: Henning Ottmann, op. cit., pp. 152–182Google Scholar
  85. 73a.
    H. Kiesewetter, Von Hegel zu Hitler (Hamburg, 1974) pp. 213 ff. — For the opposition of this ‘movement’ to an Enlightenment Hegel see especially: Julius Binder, Die Gerechtigkeit als Lebensprinzip des Staates (Langensalza, 1926) pp. 42 ff.Google Scholar
  86. 74.
    Cp.: Willi Oelmüller, Die unbefriedigte Aufklärung. Beiträge zu einer Theorie der Moderne von Lessing, Kant und Hegel (Frankfurt, 1979).Google Scholar
  87. 75.
    J.M. Ripalda, The Divided Nation (Amsterdam, 1977) p. 11.Google Scholar
  88. 76.
    Justus Schwarz, “Dokumente aus Hegels Frühzeit...”, op. cit., p. 418.Google Scholar
  89. 77.
    Cp.: J. Hoffmeister, DHE, p. IX; Paul Chamley, Économie Politique et Philosophie chez Steuart et Hegel (Paris, 1963) p. 8 (mottos) & p. 140.Google Scholar
  90. 78.
    Peter Gay, The Enlightenment — An Interpretation. In 2 vols. (London, 2nd edition, 1973) Vol. I, pp. XII & 3 ff.Google Scholar
  91. 79.
    From the wealth of available literature, I only wish to mention two older studies: H. Trescher, Montesquieus Einftuβ auf die philosophischen Grundlagen der Staatslehre Hegels (Leipzig, 1920)Google Scholar
  92. 79a.
    H.W. Brann, Rousseaus Einfluβ auf die Hegeische Staatsphilosophie in ihrer Entwicklung und Vollendung (Berlin, 1926).Google Scholar
  93. 80.
    Cp.: Horst Höhne, “Hegel und England”, Kant-Studien, Vol. XXXVI (Berlin, 1931) pp. 301–326, here p. 301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  94. 81.
    Horst Höhne, op. cit., passim; Franz Rosenzweig, Hegel und der Staat. In 2 vols. (Berlin & München, 1920) = Reprint in 1 vol. (Aalen, 1962) Vol. I, pp. 52 f., 114, Vol. II, pp. 228 f.Google Scholar
  95. 82.
    MS, Hegels Vorlesungen zur Geschichte der Philosophie [1825/1826] nach der Mitschrift von Helcel. Quoted by kind permission of the present owner: The Polish Academy of Science at Cracow, MS, No.: 57, p. 15.Google Scholar
  96. 83.
    Hegel, Vorlesungenüber dıe Geschichte der Philosophie, TWA, Vol. XX, pp. 275–281 (Hume), 281–286 (Reid, Beattie, Oswald), 285 (Ferguson & Smith).Google Scholar
  97. 84.
    Karl Marx, Oekonomisch-Philosophische Manuskripte [written in 1844]. First pub lished in: D. Riazanov (Ed.), Karl Marx- Friedrich Engels: Historisch-Kritische Gesamt ausgabe. Section I, Vol. 3 (1932). Various modern editions and English translations.Google Scholar
  98. 85.
    See above, p. 11 note 40.Google Scholar
  99. 86.
    His report of the commentary (1844, p. 86) makes it at least highly plausible that he still had it at hand.Google Scholar
  100. 87.
    Georg Lukács, Der junge Hegel. First published in 1948, but written some 10 years earlier. I have used the third German edition (Frankfurt, 1973) and the English translation by Rodney Livingstone (London, 1975).Google Scholar
  101. 88.
    Lukács (1975) title of chapter one.Google Scholar
  102. 89.
    ibid., Livingstone translation, p. 3Google Scholar
  103. 90.
    Ernst Bloch, Subjekt — Objekt (Frankfurt, 3rd edition, 1972) p. 51Google Scholar
  104. 91.
    Not only the later Marxists, but also such studies as Gunther Rohrmoser’s Subjektivitat und Verdinglichung (Gutersloh, 1961) are clearly indebted to Lukács.Google Scholar
  105. 92.
    Lukács/Livingstone, p. 101; for a criticism of this view, see Otto Pöggeler, Hegels Idee einer Phänomenologie des Geistes (Freiburg, 1973) pp. 22 f.; Henning Ottmann, op. cit., p. 89Google Scholar
  106. 93.
    For example, Lukács repeats Marx’ mistake that Ferguson was Smith’s teacher, Livingstone translation, p. 329Google Scholar
  107. 94.
    See: Otto Pöggeler, “Review of Joachim Ritter’s ‘Metaphysik and Politik”, HS, Vol. VII (Bonn, 1972) pp. 282 ff.; Henning Ottmann, op. cit., pp. 299–346Google Scholar
  108. 94a.
    also Jürgen Habermas, Theorie und Praxis (Frankfurt, 3rd ed., 1974) pp. 128–147.Google Scholar
  109. 95.
    Joachim Ritter, Hegel und die französische Revolution, first published: (Köln, 1957). I have used the third edition (Frankfurt, 1972); J.R., “Subjektivität und industrielle Gesellschaft. Zu Hegels Theorie der Subjektivitat” (1961), now in J.R., Subjektivitat (Frankfurt, 1974). I have used this latter edition.Google Scholar
  110. 96.
    J. Ritter (1972) pp. 29 ff. — Ritter’s italics have been omitted.Google Scholar
  111. 97.
    J. Ritter (1974) p. 16 — Ritter’s italics have been omitted.Google Scholar
  112. 98.
    J. Ritter (1972) pp. 52 ff; (1974) p. 25.Google Scholar
  113. 99.
    Manfred Riedel, “Die Rezeption der Nationalökonomie”, Studien zu Hegels Rechts philosophie (Frankfurt, 1969) pp. 75–99.Google Scholar
  114. 100.
    Cp.: Henning Ottmann, p. 299: “... the Western ‘liberal’ interpretation of Hegel as the proponent of the ‘modern’, democratic, constitutional state has been brought to the forefront of attention in Germany by Joachim Ritter, to such an extent that the middle- of-the-road Hegel interpretation has become almost the orthodox creed in academic circles.”Google Scholar
  115. 101.
    Paul Chamley, Économie politique et philosophie chez Steuart et Hegel (Paris, 1963).Google Scholar
  116. 102.
    Paul Chamley, “Les Origines de la Pensée Économique de Hegel”, HS, Vol. III (Bonn, 1965) pp. 225–261; P.C., “La Doctrine Économique de Hegel et la Conception Hégélienne du Travail”, HSBh 4 (Bonn, 1969) pp. 147–159.Google Scholar
  117. 103.
    Shlomo Avineri, Hegel’s Theory of the Modern State (Cambridge, 1972)Google Scholar
  118. 104.
    ibid., pp. 4–5, 142 (for Steuart); pp. 5, 93, 142, 146 ff. (for Smith); p. 141 note (for Ferguson).Google Scholar
  119. 105.
    ibid., pp. 190 ff. & 179–184Google Scholar
  120. 106.
    Duncan Forbes, “Hegel’s Theory of the State (Review of Avineri)”, Cambridge Review, March 1973, pp. 120 ff.Google Scholar
  121. 107.
    Otto Pöggeler, “Comment on Avineri’s ‘Labor, Alienation, and Social Classes in Hegel’s Realphilosophie’ ”, J.J. O’Malley and others (Eds.), The Legacy of Hegel (The Hague,1973) pp. 216–219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  122. 108.
    Raymond Plant, Hegel (London, 1973).Google Scholar
  123. 109.
    ibid., p. 57 noteGoogle Scholar
  124. 110.
    Raymond Plant, “Economic and Social Integration in Hegel’s Political Philosophy”, D.P. Verene (Ed.), Hegels Social and Political Thought (Atlantic Highlands N.J. & Brighton, Sussex, 1980) pp. 59–90Google Scholar
  125. 110a.
    R. Plant, “Hegel and Political Economy”, Part I: New Left Review No.: 103 (May 1977) pp. 79–92, Part II: New Left Review No.: 104 (July 1977) pp.103–113.Google Scholar
  126. 111.
    R. Plant (1980) p. 68.Google Scholar
  127. 112.
    Although he does mention the constructive development of one of Hegel’s answers (charity) among the British Hegelians, especially Bosanquet and Green. — Another type of answer that seems to have been in Hegel’s mind is the self-help among the members of the corporation (Philosophy of Right, Paragraph 253).Google Scholar
  128. 113.
    Bernard Cullen, Hegels Social and Political Thought (Dublin, 1979). Cp. my review of Cullen’s book, in: HS, Vol. XVIII (1983) pp. 417–419.Google Scholar
  129. 114.
    ibid., p. 3: “... the growing awareness, from about 1770 on, of the works of the historians and political economists of the Scottish Enlightenment. The writings of Adam Ferguson (1723–1816) and John Millar (1735–1801), in particular, on the development of modern commercial society and the ‘division of labour’ in history, provided their German readers with tools for the analysis of their contemporary predicament.” — Compare: Plant (1973) p. 17: “Finally the growing awareness, after about 1770, of the great works of the thinkers of the Scottish Enlightenment on the development of commercial society, particularly the writings of Adam Ferguson and John Millar, provided them with a diagnosis of the contemporary malaise and made them more aware than they had been previously of the difficulties involved in any attempt to reform the situation.”Google Scholar
  130. 115.
    Karl-Heinz Ilting (Ed.), G.W.F. Hegel: Vorlesungen über Rechtsphilosophie, 1818–1831. In 4 vols. (Stuttgart, 1973 ff.).Google Scholar
  131. 116.
    Günther Rohrmoser, Subjektivität und Verdinglichung. Theologie und Gesellschaft im Denken des jungen Hegel (Gutersloh, 1961) p. 85 and note 76; cp.: Ottmann, pp. 347 f.Google Scholar
  132. 117.
    ibid., p. 25.Google Scholar
  133. 118.
    ibid., p. 113: “The complete return from total renunciation (‘Entauβerung’) to the concrete being of society is, however, achieved by the self-conscious spirit, in command of its own substance, in religion. This is the place of reconciliation...”Google Scholar
  134. 119.
    Cp.: Heinz Kimmerle, “Zur theologischen Hegelinterpretation”, HS, Vol. III (Bonn, 1965) pp. 356–369.Google Scholar
  135. 120.
    G.W.F. Hegel, Fragmente über Volksreligion und Christentum (1793/94). TWA, Vol. I, pp. 9–103, here p. 27.Google Scholar
  136. 121.
    H.J. Krüger, Theologie und Aufklärung. Untersuchungen zu ihrer Vermittlung beim jungen Hegel (Stuttgart, 1966).Google Scholar
  137. 122.
    Peter Cornehl, Die Zukunft der Versöhnung. Eschatologie und Emanzipation in der Aufklärung, bei Hegel und in der Hegeischen Schule (Göttingen, 1971).Google Scholar
  138. 123.
    Cornehl, op. cit., pp. 160–62; compare the critical review by Walther Zimmerli, “Hegel und die Zukunft der Religion”, HS, Vol. VIII (Bonn, 1973) pp. 267–276.Google Scholar
  139. 124.
    Cornehl, pp. 29–59.Google Scholar
  140. 125.
    J.M. Ripalda (1977) and compare his earlier article: “‘Poesie und Politik’ beim frühen Hegel”, HS, Vol. VIII (Bonn, 1973) pp. 91–118. — In contrast to the scholarly article, the book contains rather a lot of misprints as well as more serious mistakes, a fact that may be explained, if not excused, by the circumstances: a German manuscript, written by a Spaniard, translated into American English, published and printed in Holland.Google Scholar
  141. 126.
    Ripalda (1977) p. 11: “By focusing on Hegel, the great bourgeois thinker, we hope to shed some light on the often opaque and confusing cultural traditions of bourgeois society”. — Cp.: p. 22 and dust jacket.Google Scholar
  142. 127.
    H.S. Harris (1972); F. Nicolin, Der junge Hegel in Stuttgart (Stuttgart, 1970)Google Scholar
  143. 127a.
    Otto Pöggeler (1973) & “Hegels praktische Philosophie in Frankfurt”, HS, Bd. IX (Bonn, 1974) pp. 73–107.Google Scholar
  144. 128.
    Some of the historical causes of the Scottish Enlightenment, touched upon in this section, are developed more fully in my Stirling M. Litt. Thesis: “Man’s Social Nature: A Topic of the Scottish Enlightenment in its Historical Setting” (University of Stirling, submitted in November 1979).Google Scholar
  145. 129.
    Bernhard Suphan (Ed.), Herders Sämtliche Werke. 33 in 25 vols. (Berlin, 1877–1913); here: Vol. V (Berlin, 1891) p. 452.Google Scholar
  146. 131.
    Lord Karnes, for example, was instrumental in organizing Smith’s lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres (1748–1751).Google Scholar
  147. 132.
    T.C. Smout, A History of the Scottish People 1560–1830 (Glasgow and London, 4th impression, 1972) p. 478.Google Scholar
  148. 133.
    For that later part of the story, cp.: G.E. Davie, The Democratic Intellect (Edin burgh, 1961), a milestone in Scottish cultural history.Google Scholar
  149. 134.
    This phrase is from Joseph de Maistre, and Nicholas Phillipson used it himself: N.P., “Towards a Definition of the Scottish Enlightenment”, P. Fritz & D. Williams (Eds.), City and Society in the Eighteenth Century (Toronto, 1973) pp. 125–147, here p. 125.Google Scholar
  150. 135.
    The Letters of David Hume. Edited by J.Y.T. Greig. In 2 vols. (Oxford, 1932) Vol. I, p. 255.Google Scholar
  151. 136.
    With respect to Hume, surveys of modern scholarly support of the Newtonian influence can be found in James Noxon, Hume’s Philosophical Development (Oxford, 2nd edition, 1975) pp. 27–33Google Scholar
  152. 136a.
    cp.: Nicholas Capaldi, David Hume (Boston, 1975) p. 233.Google Scholar
  153. 137.
    John Millar, An Historical View of the English Government. In 4 vols. (London, 1812) Vol. II, pp. 429–30 n.Google Scholar
  154. 138.
    The Collected Works of Dugald Stewart. Edited by Sir William Hamilton. In XI vols. (Edinburgh, 1854–60) Vol. I, p. 551. — Henceforth quoted as “DSt”.Google Scholar
  155. 139.
    DSt, Vol. X, p. 82; also in SGE, Vol. III, pp. 269–351, here p. 334: “His [Hutche- son’s] great and deserved fame, however, in this country, rests now chiefly on the traditionary history of his Academical Lectures, which appear to have contributed very powerfully to diffuse, in Scotland, that taste for analytical discussion, and that spirit of liberal inquiry, to which the world is indebted for some of the most valuable productions of the eighteenth century.” — Cp.: DSt, Vol. I, p. 428.Google Scholar
  156. 140.
    W.R. Scott, Francis Hutcheson. His Life, Teaching and Position in the History of Philosophy (Cambridge, 1900) = [Reprint: New York, 1966] here p. 266.Google Scholar
  157. 141.
    In: R.H. Campbell & A.S. Skinner (Eds.), The Origins and Nature of the Scottish Enlightenment (Edinburgh, 1982) pp. 167–185.Google Scholar
  158. 142.
    DSt, Vol. X, p. 35; also in SGE, Vol. III, p. 294.Google Scholar
  159. 143.
    For a short introduction to this field and recommendations for further reading, see: P. Smith, The Enlightenment 1687–1776 [1934], now ed. by Crane Brinton (London & New York, 1966) pp. 140–47, 558–60.Google Scholar
  160. 144.
    R.L. Meek, “The Scottish Contribution to Marxist Sociology” [1954], now in: R.L.M., Economics and Ideology and other Essays (London, 1967) pp. 34–50, especially p. 47; cp.: R.L.M., Social Science and the Ignoble Savage (Cambridge, 1976).Google Scholar
  161. 145.
    H.T. Buckle, The History of Civilization in England. In 2 vols. (London, 1857–61)Google Scholar
  162. 145a.
    I have used the following modern edition of the Scottish sections: H.J. Hanham (Ed.), Buckle on Scotland and the Scottish Intellect (Chicago & London, 1970) p. 235: “When the contest was ended, and peace was restored, the faculties which, for three generations, had been exercised in resisting the executive authority, sought other employment, and found another field in which they could disport themselves.” — Cp.: James McCosh, The Scottish Philosophy (London, 1875) = [Reprint: Hildesheim, 1966] p. 21: “It could have appeared only in a time of peace and temporal prosperity, but there had been a preparation for it in the prior struggles. The stream which had risen in a higher region, and long pursued its course in ruggedness, — like the rivers of the country, — is now flowing through more level ground, and raising up plenty on its banks.”Google Scholar
  163. 146.
    Millar, 1812, Vol. III, pp. 88 f.; cp.: Macaulay who singled out the parish school act [1696] to account for the great progress of learning among the Scots: Thomas Babington, Baron Macaulay, The History of England. I have used an edition in 8 vols. (London, 1858–62) Vol. VII, p. 415.Google Scholar
  164. 147.
    H.E. Barnes, “Sociology before Comte”, American Journal of Sociology (Chicago, 1917) Vol. XXIII, pp. 174–247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  165. 148.
    In: M. Palyi (Ed.), Hauptprobleme der Soziologie. Erinnerungsgabe für Max Weber (München & Leipzig, 1923) pp. 5–19.Google Scholar
  166. 149.
    W.C. Lehmann, Adam Ferguson and the Beginnings of Modern Sociology (Chicago, 1930)Google Scholar
  167. 149a.
    Roy Pascal, “Property and Society: The Scottish Historical School of the Eigh teenth Century”, The Modern Quarterly (London, 1938) Vol. I, pp. 167–179Google Scholar
  168. 149b.
    Gladys Bryson, Man and Society. The Scottish Inquiry of the Eighteenth Century (Princeton, 1945) = [Reprint: New York, 1968].Google Scholar
  169. 150.
    D.D. Raphael, The Moral Sense (Oxford, 1947). The work discusses Hutcheson, Hume, Price, and Reid.Google Scholar
  170. 151.
    T.D. Campbell, Adam Smith’s Science of Morals (London, 1971)Google Scholar
  171. 151a.
    H. Jensen, Motivation and the Moral Sense in Francis Hutcheson (The Hague, 1971).Google Scholar
  172. 152.
    For general accounts, see: P. Gay, The Enlightenment: An Interpretation. Vol. II: The Science of Freedom (London, 2nd edition, 1973) pp. 290–318Google Scholar
  173. 152a.
    Ernst Cassirer, The Philosophy of the Enlightenment [1932]. I have used the English edition (Princeton, 1951) pp. 312–331.Google Scholar
  174. 153.
    See their introduction to Smith’s “Theory of Moral Sentiments”, SGE, Vol. I, pp. 5–10; and cp.: A.L. Macfie’s earlier article: “The Scottish Tradition in Economic Thought”, Scottish Journal of Political Economy. Vol. II (Edinburgh, 1955) pp. 81–103, especially pp. 82, 86 ff.Google Scholar
  175. 154.
    Cp.: Wealth and Virtue: the Shaping of Political Economy in the Scottish Enlightenment. Ed. by Istvan Hont and Michael Ignatieff (Cambridge, 1983).Google Scholar
  176. 155.
    I have tried to clarify some elements of this impact in my article: “Two Concepts of Morality: a Distinction of Adam Smith’s Ethics and its Stoic Origin”, Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. XLV, 4 (October 1984) pp. 591–606.Google Scholar
  177. 156.
    J.G.A. Pocock, “Cambridge Paradigms and Scotch Philosophers”, in: Wealth and Virtue..., op. cit., pp. 249 f.Google Scholar
  178. 157.
    Cp.: William Ferguson, History of Scotland, 1689-today (Edinburgh, 1968) p. 86.Google Scholar
  179. 158.
    H.G. Graham, Scottish Men of Letters in the Eighteenth Century (London, 1901); cp.: Alexander Carlyle, Autobiography (Edinburgh, 1860).Google Scholar
  180. 159.
    The early version of this thesis: ‘“Scientific Whiggism: Adam Smith and John Millar”, The Cambridge Journal, Vol. VII (1954) pp. 643–670, grew into more detailed applications of it to Hume: D.F., Hume’s Philosophical Politics (Cambridge, 1975), and to Smith: D.F., “Sceptical Whiggism, Commerce, and Liberty”, A.S. Skinner & T. Wilson (Eds.), Essays on Adam Smith (Oxford, 1975) pp. 179–201.Google Scholar
  181. 160.
    D. Forbes, “Natural Law and the Scottish Enlightenment”, R.H. Campbell & A.S. Skinner (Eds.), The Origins and Nature of the Scottish Enlightenment (Edinburgh, 1982) pp. 186–204, here p. 193. — To some extent, this program has been followed up indepen dently by Knud Haakonssen: The Science of a Legislator (Cambridge, 1981).Google Scholar
  182. 161.
    Cp. G.E. Davie, “Berkeley’s Impact on Scottish Philosophers”, Philosophy. Vol. XL (1965) pp. 222–234; and his recent: “Berkeley, Hume, and the Central Problem of Scottish Philosophy”, McGill Hume Studies. Ed. by D.F. Norton and others (San Diego, 1979) pp. 43–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  183. 162.
    G.E. Davie, “Anglophobe and Anglophil”, Scottish Journal of Political Economy Vol. XIV (1967) pp. 291–302, here p. 295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  184. 163.
    G.E. Davie, “Hume, Reid, and the Passion of Ideas”, Edinburgh in the Age of Reason (Edinburgh, 1967) pp. 23–39, here pp. 33 f.Google Scholar
  185. 164.
    Sir James Steuart, An Inquiry into the Principles of Political Economy. In 2 vols. Edited by A.S. Skinner (Edinburgh, 1966); A.S. Skinner, “Sir James Steuart: Economics and Politics”, “Money and Prices: A Critique of the Quantity Theory”, “Sir James Steuart: Author of a System”, all in Scottish Journal of Political Economy. Vol. IX, XIV, and XXVIII respectively.Google Scholar
  186. 165.
    A.S. Skinner, “Economics and History — The Scottish Enlightenment”, Scottish Journal of Political Economy (1965) Vol. XII, pp. 1–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  187. 166.
    A.S. Skinner, A System of Social Science. Papers relating to Adam Smith (Oxford, 1979).Google Scholar
  188. 167.
    H.S. Harris, Hegels Development II: Night Thoughts (Jena 1801–1806) (Oxford, 1983) p. xxxi.Google Scholar
  189. 168.
    Peter Gay (1973) II, p. 131.Google Scholar
  190. 169.
    F.M.A. de Voltaire, Elements de la philosophie de Newton (London, 1738).Google Scholar
  191. 170.
    For a survey of the scientific achievements of the Scottish Enlightenment, see: A.C. Chitnis, The Scottish Enlightenment (London, 1976) pp. 124–194.Google Scholar
  192. 171.
    James Noxon, Hume’s Philosophical Development (Oxford, 2nd ed., 1975) p. 69.Google Scholar
  193. 172.
    David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature. Ed. by L.A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford, 1888) p. 639 — henceforth quoted as “Treatise”Google Scholar
  194. 173.
    In the introduction to his critical edition of Smith’s essays, SGE, Vol. III, p. 21.Google Scholar
  195. 174.
    J. Noxon (1975) p 112Google Scholar
  196. 175.
    J. Noxon (1975); Nicholas Capaldi, David Hume (Boston, 1975).Google Scholar
  197. 176.
    John Passmore, Hume’s Intentions (Cambridge, 1952) especially p. 43Google Scholar
  198. 176a.
    T.E. Jessop, “Some misunderstandings of Hume”, V.C. Chappel (Ed.), Hume (London, 1968) pp. 46 f.Google Scholar
  199. 177.
    Isaac Newton, Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica (London, 1687). I have used the German edition: Mathematische Prinzipien der Naturlehre, edited by J. Ph. Wolfers (Berlin, 1872). The English translation is quoted from N. Capaldi (1975) p. 61.Google Scholar
  200. 178.
    N. Capaldi (1975) p. 67.Google Scholar
  201. 179.
    T.E. Jessop (1968) p. 47Google Scholar
  202. 180.
    J. Noxon (1975) p. 21.Google Scholar
  203. 181.
    Norman Kemp Smith, The Philosophy of David Hume (London, 1941) p. 59.Google Scholar
  204. 182.
    J. Noxon (1975) p. 24 — The same distinction between Hume’s concepts of sympathy is made by D.G.C. Macnabb, David Hume. His Theory of Knowledge and Morality (Oxford, 2nd ed., 1966) p. 191.Google Scholar
  205. 183.
    N.K. Smith (1941) p. 76.Google Scholar
  206. 184.
    Cp.: J. Noxon (1975) pp. 16–26; 108–123; 188–192.Google Scholar
  207. 185.
    “Treatise”, op. cit., p. xvi: “... the only solid foundation we can give to this science [of man]... must be laid on experience and observation.” — N.K. Smith (1941) p. 62: “... for Hume, the term ‘experimentar’ is virtually equivalent to the term ‘empirical’, but is a stronger term, carrying with it the suggestion of a deliberate collecting of observations, sufficient in number and more especially in variety, to serve as a reliable basis for generalization.”Google Scholar
  208. 186.
    The Letters of David Hume. In 2 vols., edited by J.Y.T. Greig (Oxford, 1932) Vol. I, p. 16.Google Scholar
  209. 187.
    Isaac Newton, Opticks, Or a Treatise of the Reflections, Inflections and Colours of Light (London, 1704), quoted from J. Noxon (1975) pp. 63 f.Google Scholar
  210. 188.
    J.H. Randall, “The Development of Scientific Method in the School of Padua”, JHI, Vol. I (1940) pp. 177–206CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  211. 188a.
    J.H. Randall, The School of Padua (Padova, 1961).Google Scholar
  212. 189.
    The following discussion uses the results of A.S. Skinner (1979) and Richard Olson, Scottish Philosophy and British Physics, 1750–1880 (Oxford, 1975).Google Scholar
  213. 190.
    Cp.: Karl Rosenkranz (1844) pp. 151 ff; Kuno Fischer, Hegels Leben, Werke und Lehre. [1901]. In 2 vols. (Heidelberg, 3rd edition, 1963) Vol. I, pp. 235, 469 ff, 478 f, Vol. II, pp. 583,585, 605 ff, 1129.Google Scholar
  214. 191.
    The carefully annotated edition of Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature, in 3 vols., edited by M.J. Petry (London, 1970) was crucial in initiating this revival. Henceforth, this edition will be quoted as “MJP”.Google Scholar
  215. 192.
    Cp.: Otto Closs, Kepler und Newton und das Problem der Gravitation in der Kantischen, Schellingschen und He gelschen Naturphilosophie (Heidelberg, 1908)Google Scholar
  216. 192a.
    Erhard Oeser, “Der Gegensatz von Kepler und Newton in Hegels absoluter Mechanik”, Wiener Jahrbuch fur Philosophie, Vol. III (1979) pp. 69–93Google Scholar
  217. 192b.
    M.J. Petry, “Hegels kritiek op Newton”, Wijsgerig Perspectief, Vol. 22 (1981/1982) pp. 103–111 and his forthcoming “Hegel’s Criticism of Newton”, will appear in Clio, Vol. 12, 4 (1985)Google Scholar
  218. 192c.
    Hans-Jürgen Treder, “Hegel zu den Begriffen ‘Schwere’, ‘Trägheit’, ‘Masse’ und ‘Kraft’”, Vom Mute des Erkennens. Beitrage zur Philosophie G.W.F. Hegels. Ed. by M. Buhr & T.I. Oisermann (Frankfurt, 1981) pp. 204–211Google Scholar
  219. 192d.
    Henry Paolucci, “Hegel and the Celestial Mechanics of Newton and Einstein” & M. Capek, “Hegel and the Organic View of Nature”, both in: Hegel and the Sciences, ed. by R.S. Cohen & M.W. Wartofsky (Dordrecht, 1984) pp. 55–85 & 109–121.Google Scholar
  220. 193.
    Rosenkranz (1844) p. 151; this evidence can now be supplemented by the data from the auction catalogue of Hegel’s library according to which Hegel possessed the following Newton editions: Isaaci Newtoni, Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica (Amster dam, 1714); Optice (London, 1719)Google Scholar
  221. 193a.
    MacLaurini, Expositionae philosophiae Newtoniae (Vindobonae, 1761), cp.: HBibl, p. 53, No.: 1299, 1301, 1302.Google Scholar
  222. 194.
    Cp.: HGW, Vol. XI, pp. 166 f.; Vol. XXI, pp. 252 f.Google Scholar
  223. 195.
    Cp.: J. Russel, S.J., “Kepler’s Laws of Planetary Motion, 1609–1666”, British Journal of the History of Science, Vol. II (1964) pp. 1–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  224. 196.
    In his summary of developmental studies of Newton, Preserved Smith concludes, A History of Modern Culture, in 2 vols., with an introduction by Crane Brinton (New York & London, 1962) Vol. II, p. 40: “... the reading of Kepler’s Optics opened his [Newton’s] mind to the wonders of physics. The acquisition of this book was the crucial date in his development. From the German scientist, whose influence over him can hardly be exaggerated, he obtained the starting-point for his investigations...”Google Scholar
  225. 197.
    Adam Smith’s comment that the “... generous and magnificent Dane [Tycho Brahe] invited the obscure and indigent Kepler...” (SGE, Vol. III, p. 85, my own emphasis; N.W.) provides a suitable example of this tendency.Google Scholar
  226. 198.
    For scientific discussions of Newton’s conception of matter, see: A.J. Snow, Matter and Gravity in Newton’s Physical Philosophy (Oxford, 1926)Google Scholar
  227. 198a.
    A.R. Hall and M.B. Hall, “Newton’s Theory of Matter”, Isis (1960) pp 131–144.Google Scholar
  228. 199.
    G.W.F. Hegel, Dissertationi philosophicae de orbitis planetarum praemissae theses (Jena, 1801). Now accessible and quoted from Rosenkranz (1844) pp. 156–159, here: Thesis I, p. 156.Google Scholar
  229. 200.
    Cp.: J.N. Findlay, Hegel — A Re-Examination (London, 1958) p. 348:... despite much opinion to the contrary, Hegel’s philosophy is one of the most anti-metaphysical of philosophical systems, one that remains most within the pale of ordinary experience...”; Duncan Forbes in HBN, p. xiii: “... the philosophy of the Absolute is absolutely open to experience... as empirical as any empiricist should wish... but sense experience, in itself and as such, cannot be the full truth about reality, and if one tries to make it so, the result is self-contradiction... nevertheless all the rungs on the ladder of experience which ends with philosophy are rungs in the ladder of philosophy, and that means that they are in themselves perfectly valid, necessary aspects of truth. An exposition of the opposing view can be found in Prof. A.R. Manser’s forthcoming review of Hegel and the Sciences, op cit. I am grateful to Prof. Manser for making his article available to me.Google Scholar
  230. 201.
    In his forthcoming article “Metaphysik in den Naturwissenschaften”, will appear in Natur und Subjektivität. Ed. by R. Heckmann et al., Wolfgang Neuser defends Hegel’s position in greater detail.Google Scholar
  231. 202.
    For an assessment of Bode’s “law” by modern scientists, see: Hannes Alfvén & Gustaf Arrhenius, Evolution of the Solar System (Washington, D.C., 1976) chapter 2.6, p. 33, where further references can be found.Google Scholar
  232. 203.
    H.E.G. Paulus, for example, thought it proper to ridicule the deceased Hegel, his former friend, in this manner: Entdeckungen über die Entdeckungen der neuesten Philosophen (Bremen, 1835) pp. 23 ff.Google Scholar
  233. 204.
    Giuseppe Piazzi, Risultati delle osservazioni della nuova Stella scoperta il primo gennajo 1801 (Palermo, August 1801) and Della scoperta del nuova planeta Cerere Ferdinandea (Palermo, 1802); cp.: MJP, Vol. I, pp. 370 f. In his recent investigation: “Wissenschaftstheoretische Überlegungen zu Hegels Planetenschrift”, Hegel-Studien, Vol. XVIII (1984) pp. 65–137, T.G. Bucher comes to a different result. I cannot here enter into a full-length critique of Bucher’s article, but the fact that he neither mentions Piazzi’s own writings nor Prof. Petry’s seminal research does not inspire much confidence in his work.Google Scholar
  234. 205.
    Karl Rosenkranz (1844) p. 155. In my reading of Hegel’s later Jena lectures — the best and most complete edition is HGW, Vols. VI, VII, VIII — I have not come across a reference to ‘Ceres’, but Rosenkranz was able to consult manuscripts that have been lost since then.Google Scholar
  235. 206.
    G.W.F. Hegel, Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (Heidelberg, 1817) § 224, p. 159.Google Scholar
  236. 207.
    TWA: Vol VI, pp 502–541; Vol. VIII, §§ 226–231, pp. 379–385.Google Scholar
  237. 208.
    M.J. Petry, “Hegel’s Criticism of the Ethics of Kant and Fichte”, in: L.S. Stepele-vich & David Lamb (Eds.), Hegel’s Philosophy of Action (Atlantic Highlands, N.J., 1983) pp. 125–136.Google Scholar
  238. 209.
    Petry (1983) p. 131.Google Scholar
  239. 210.
    Petry (1983) pp. 132 f.Google Scholar
  240. 211.
    MJP, Vol. I, p. 114: “For Hegel... the Idea of Nature involves a combination of the Baconian and the Boehmian attitudes to natural phenomena. Despite the searching criticism of Newtonian mechanics and optics contained in these lectures [sc: the lectures of the philosophy of nature], the basic inspiration of the work may therefore be regarded as differing little, if at all, from that of the ‘Principia Mathematica’.”Google Scholar
  241. 212.
    Cp.: MJP, Vol. I: pp. 250, 265, 272 and see Petry’s notes: ibid., pp. 329 f., 351 f., 362 f.)Google Scholar
  242. 214.
    Cp.: Ludwig Siep’s forthcoming “Hegels Theorie der Gewaltenteilung”, in: Hans-Christian Lucas & Otto Pöggeler (Eds.), Hegels Rechtsphilosophie im Zusammenhang der europäischen Verfassungsgeschichte (Stuttgart, 1986). Prof. Siep argues convincingly that Hegel’s views ought to be seen as a conscious revision of the ancient correspondence between ‘cosmos’ and ‘polis’.Google Scholar
  243. 215.
    Although this quotation is taken from Gans’ addition to §189 (TMK p. 268), it has been confirmed by the edition of von Griesheim’s lecture notes: VRP, Vol. IV, pp. 486 f.Google Scholar
  244. 216.
    Duncan Forbes, Hume’s Philosophical Politics (Cambridge, 1975) p. viii.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht 1988

Authors and Affiliations

  • Norbert Waszek
    • 1
  1. 1.Hegel-Archiv der Ruhr UniversitätBochumGermany

Personalised recommendations