Skip to main content

Reid and Peirce on Belief

  • Chapter
The Philosophy of Thomas Reid

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 42))

  • 143 Accesses

Abstract

The influence Thomas Reid exerted on C.S. Peirce is well known. (1) The American founder of pragmatism more than once recognized his debt to the Scottish philosopher.(2) Reid’s theory of immediate perception, his sophisticated realism, and many aspects of his Common Sense approach are almost entirely adopted by Peirce,(3) who also stresses the acuteness and precision of Reid’s analyses in psychology,(4) while he blames Hamilton for his frequent errors of interpretation.(5)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. See, for example, Feibleman (1944, pp. 113–20) and Flower (1980, pp. 94–103). Reid, with Berkeley, Kant and Bain, was a favourite author for discussion among the group including Green, James and Peirce which was to found the ‘Metaphysical Club’ from which pragmatism arose. Peirce himself admitted that pragmatism was but a ‘corollary’ of Bain’s definition of belief. See Fisch (1954, pp. 413–44).

    Google Scholar 

  2. See, for example, Peirce (1931–1958; I, 19, 38, 240; V, 56, 444, 523, 539, 608; VII, 580n; VIII, 123n, 261). References are given by volume and paragraph number.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Peirce (1931–1958; V, 444, 523; VI, 95; VIII, 261).

    Google Scholar 

  4. For example, Peirce (1931–1958; V, 444) describes Reid as “a subtle but well-balanced intellect”, and (VIII, 123n) as “a singularly accurate observer, whose lessons have not yet been thoroughly learned by psychologists”. Further, (ibid.) Peirce cites Reid as having been the first “distinctly to recognise that we have something like a direct perception of duration, or at least, of motion” and to “draw the needful distinction between the lapse of time during the act of perception and the lapse of time represented in the percept”.

    Google Scholar 

  5. For example, Peirce (1931–1958; I, 38) writes how “Hamilton stupidly objects to Reid’s phrase ‘immediate memory’”. Peirce’s criticism merits recognition, since he anticipated the view which was later to emerge of Hamilton’s responsibility for errors of interpretation and the relative disaffection Reid’s philosophy was to undergo. See Greenberg (1976) or Brody (1971).

    Google Scholar 

  6. See, for example, some judgments by Grave (1960) or Griffen-Collard (1979).

    Google Scholar 

  7. IP, II, xx (Works, pp. 327–8).

    Google Scholar 

  8. IP, II, xx (Works, p. 327). See also I, II, v (Works, p. 107).

    Google Scholar 

  9. IP, II, xxi (Works, p. 332); Cf. I, VI, xxiv (Works, p. 196).

    Google Scholar 

  10. I, VI, xx (Works, pp. 545–9).

    Google Scholar 

  11. IP, II, xx (Works, p. 327).

    Google Scholar 

  12. IP, IV, i (Works, p. 360).

    Google Scholar 

  13. I, II, v (Works, p. 107).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Peirce (1931–58; V, 487) explains its psychological meaning thus: “Multiple reiterated behaviour of the same kind, under similar combinations of percepts and fancies, produces a tendency — the habit — actually to behave in a similar way under similar circumstances in the future”. Physiologically speaking, habits are general ways of behaviour which are associated with the removal of stimuli (VI, 264); as such, they may be found in all actual things, in rivers as well as in animals, in plants as well as in crystalline substances (VI, 260).

    Google Scholar 

  15. This is scarcely different from Bain’s definition of belief as preparedness to act.

    Google Scholar 

  16. In that respect, Peirce’s definition of belief seems perfectly compatible with the attribution of beliefs to animals. See the analysis of Engel (1984, p. 408): “Ceconcept de croyance semble, dans la mesure ou l’assertion d’une proposition n’est pas necessaire a son attribution, parfaitement compatible avec l’attribution de croyances dispositionnelles a des animaux. Ainsi, l’assertion d’une proposition, un sentiment de conviction peuvent faire partie de cette conception dispositionnelle. Mais ils n’en sont nila condition necessaire ni la condition suffisante”. Compare Peirce (1931–58; II, 148): “A belief need not be conscious. When it is recognized, the act of recognition is called by logicians a judgment, although this is properly a term of psychology”.

    Google Scholar 

  17. “Every belief is belief in a proposition. Indeed, every proposition has its predicate which expresses what is believed and its subjects which express of what it is believed” (Peirce, 1931–58; V, 542). Compare Reid (IP, II, xx, Works, p. 327): “Belief is always expressed in language by a proposition, wherein something is affirmed or denied. This is the form of speech which in all languages is appropriated to that purpose, and without belief there could be neither affirmation nor denial, nor should we have any form of words to express either”.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cf. Peirce (1931–58; II, 148): “What particularly distinguishes a general belief, or opinion, such as is an inferential conclusion, from other habits, is that it is active in the imagination. If I have a habit of putting ray left leg into my trouser before the right, when I imagine that I put on my trousers, I shall probably not definitely think of putting the left leg on first. But if I believe that fire is dangerous, and I imagine a fire bursting out close beside me, I shall also imagine that I jump back”. In such a case belief involves judgment: “we virtually resolve, upon a certain occasion to act as if certain imagined circumstances were perceived” (II, 435). Thus beliefs construct imaginary conditions which “determine schemata or imaginary skeleton diagrams” (II, 148). This act “which amounts to such a resolve, is a peculiar act of the will whereby we cause an image, or icon, to be associated in a particularly strenuous way, with an object represented to us by an index. This act itself is represented in the proposition by a symbol, and the consciousness of it fulfils the function of a symbol in the judgment. Suppose, for example, I detect a person with whom I have to deal in an act of dishonesty, I have in mind something like a ‘composite photograph’ of all the persons that I have known and read of that have had that character, and at the instant I make the discovery, concerning that person, who is distinguished from others for me by certain indications, upon that index, at that moment down goes the stamp of RASCAL, to remain indefinitely”.

    Google Scholar 

  19. “It does not follow that because every theoretical belief is, at least indirectly, a practical belief, this is the whole meaning of the theoretical belief” (V, 538).

    Google Scholar 

  20. “A belief is an intelligent habit upon which we shall act when occasion presents itself” (V, 398). Cf. V, 545; V, 542.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Peirce explicitly cites Reid as illustrating the part of the unexpected necessary in accounting for the reality of ourbeliefs. Cf. Peirce (1931–58; V, 542).

    Google Scholar 

  22. Cf. note 10 supra.

    Google Scholar 

  23. AP, III, I, ii (Works, p. 545–6).

    Google Scholar 

  24. AP, III, I, i (Works, p. 545).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  26. ( AP, III, II, iii (Works, p. 550).

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  29. AP, III, I, iii (Works, pp. 550–1).

    Google Scholar 

  30. AP, II, iii (Works, p. 540).

    Google Scholar 

  31. AP, II, iii (Works, pp. 539 & 541).

    Google Scholar 

  32. AP, II, iii (Works, p. 540).

    Google Scholar 

  33. AP, II, iii (Works, p. 541).

    Google Scholar 

  34. IP, I, i (Works, p. 221).

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  36. AP, I, i (Works, pp. 512–3).

    Google Scholar 

  37. AP, I, i (Works, p. 514).

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  40. AP, I, v (Works, p. 525).

    Google Scholar 

  41. Peirce (1931–58; V, 542).

    Google Scholar 

  42. Peirce (1931–58; V, 402).

    Google Scholar 

  43. Peirce (1931–58; V, 400).

    Google Scholar 

  44. Such a conception has of course enormous consequences for the versions of Realism the two philosophers maintain. Thus Peirce holds: “To assert that a law positively exists is to assert that it will operate, and therefore to refer to the future, even though conditionally. But to say that a body is hard, or red, or heavy, or of a given weight, or has any other property, is to say that it is subject to law and therefore, is a statement referring to the future” (V, 545). So if I assert ‘This wafer looks red’, it can only mean that “so far as the character of the percept can ever be ascertained, it will be ascertained that the wafer looked red” (V, 542); and to believe that a sulphur is yellow is to say that “it would be perfectly meaningless to say that sulphur had the singular property of turning pink when nobody was looking at it” (V, 545). Compare this with the following claim by Reid: “When the parts of a body adhere so firmly that it cannot easily be made to change its figure, we call it hard; when its parts are easily displaced, we call it soft. This is the notion which all mankind have of hardness and softness; they are neither sensations, nor like any sensation; they were real qualities before they were perceived by touch, and continue to be so when they are not perceived; for if any man will affirm that diamonds were not hard till they were handled, who would reason with him?” (I, V, ii, Works, p. 120).

    Google Scholar 

  45. Peirce (1931–58; VIII, 261).

    Google Scholar 

  46. Cf. note 18 supra.

    Google Scholar 

  47. See, for example, Grave (1960, ch.5) and Rollin (1978, pp. 257–70).

    Google Scholar 

  48. I, VI, xxi, (Works, p. 188); I, VI, xxiv (Works, pp. 194, 196, 199).

    Google Scholar 

  49. I, VI, xx (Works, pp. 183, 209); IP, I, ii (Works, p. 231); II, v (Works, pp. 258–60); VI, v (Works, p. 445). This is what Peirce calls the category of secondness. Cf. Peirce (1931–58; VII, 643; VII, 635, VII, 619; IV, 57; III, 361 et al.).

    Google Scholar 

  50. I, II, v (Works, p. 107); IP, VI, vi (Works, pp. 454–5).

    Google Scholar 

  51. I, VI, xxiv (Works, p. 198); IP, VI, v (Works, p. 443).

    Google Scholar 

  52. I, VI, xxiv (Works, pp. 196–7); IP, VI, iv (Works, p. 438); VI, v (Works, p. 450).

    Google Scholar 

  53. See ‘The Fixation of Belief’ (1878) in Peirce (1931–58; V, 358–87) and especially 377–81. To these methods, Peirce opposes the only method which may now apply to the state of knowledge, the Scientific Method.

    Google Scholar 

  54. This is a very important theme in Peirce’s philosophy. Cf. Peirce (1931–58; V, 265, 319; VIII, 16 et al.).

    Google Scholar 

  55. I, II, vii (Works, p. 110); VI, xx (Works, p. 184).

    Google Scholar 

  56. Cf. note 6 supra. See also Griffin-Collard (1976, pp. 126–42).

    Google Scholar 

  57. This lies at the core of Reid’s discussion of universals, and especially on qualities. Are they in the mind, or in the body? Does a common name signify one or two things?

    Google Scholar 

  58. Consider, for example, the errors of interpretation we make about the natural language of signs, and confusions arising from a single name meaning different things.

    Google Scholar 

  59. ‘Questions concerning certain faculties claimed for man’, ‘Some consequences of four incapacities’, and ‘Grounds of validity of the Laws of Logic’ in Peirce (1931–58; V, 213–357).

    Google Scholar 

  60. Peirce (1931–58; V, 244–9). For a more extensive analysis of this theme, see Engel-Tiercelin (1982).

    Google Scholar 

  61. Peirce (1931–58; I, 19; V, 77n).

    Google Scholar 

  62. Cf. Peirce (1931–58; V, 508).

    Google Scholar 

  63. Peirce (1931–58; V, 523).

    Google Scholar 

  64. Peirce (1931–58; V, 511) alludes to the Darwinian themes which exercised a deep influence on him.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Fallibilism is a very important element in Peirce’s philosophy of science, as in his metaphysics. It is the doctrine that there always remains indeterminacy and vagueness, so that we can never be cocksure that today’s truth may not be falsified.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Griffin-Collard (1976, p. 141) concludes that Reid develops a ‘static’ theory of knowledge.

    Google Scholar 

  67. See, for example, I, V, iii (Works, p. 122); or IP, I, ii (Works, p. 234); or his discussion of analogy I, iv (Works, pp. 236–8); or his admission that Newton’s principle of gravitation may be wrong in so far as “it is not a necessary truth, whose contrary is impossible” (IP, VI, iv Works, p. 436).

    Google Scholar 

  68. IP, I, ii (Works, p. 233) and VI, viii (Works, pp. 468–75).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Engel-Tiercelin, C. (1989). Reid and Peirce on Belief. In: Dalgarno, M., Matthews, E. (eds) The Philosophy of Thomas Reid. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 42. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2338-6_14

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2338-6_14

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7552-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2338-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics