Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Philosophy of Engineering and Technology ((POET,volume 15))

Abstract

A crucial step in Value Sensitive Design (VSD) is the translation of values into design requirements. However, few research has been done on how this translation can be made. In this contribution, I first consider an example of this translation. I then introduce the notion of values hierarchy, a hierarchy structure of values, norms and design requirements. I discuss the relation of specification, by which values can be translated into design requirements, and the for the sake of relation which connects design requirements to underlying norms and values. I discuss conditions under which a certain specification of values into design requirements is adequate or at least tenable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    In the literature such hierarchies have been called objectives hierarchies, objectives networks or objectives trees (e.g. Keeney 1992: chapter 3; Keeney and Raiffa 1993: chapter 2; Cross 2008: chapter 6). What I call a values hierarchy below resembles what Keeney and Raiffa (1993) call an objectives hierarchy and what Cross (2008) calls an objectives tree. Keeney (1992) distinguishes between fundamental objectives hierarchies and (means-end) objectives networks. My values hierarchies come closest to the latter but allow a larger heterogeneity of relations between the elements.

  2. 2.

    Cf. Richardson (1997). In the engineering literature, specification is also used in a number of different meanings which I do not intend to imply here.

  3. 3.

    Note that it does make sense, however, to say that animal welfare is a value (partly) because chickens should have enough living space. This suggests two things. First, the relation for the sake of is not exhausted by its justificatory part that may be expressed by because and, second, the justificatory relation that is expressed by because may be bidirectional.

  4. 4.

    It is worth noting that the general conceptualization of animal welfare by ethologists in terms of the fulfillment of certain ethological needs that animals like chickens have in ‘natural’ circumstances does require very limited domain-specific knowledge. The conceptualization does not require any detailed knowledge of what these needs or what natural circumstances would be, only that these can be somehow identified. Philosophers might indeed criticize this conceptualization of animal welfare on a number of grounds. They may, for example, doubt whether there exists such a thing as ‘natural’ circumstances and, even if such circumstances would have existed, they may question why these circumstances would provide a normative yardstick (How convincing would it be to argue that killing or rape is part of human welfare or wellbeing because in ‘natural’ circumstances humans felt a need for them? Of course, animals are not humans). In fact, other conceptualizations of animal welfare are possible, for example, in terms of how animals ‘feel’, which might be measured for example in terms of stress.

  5. 5.

    In practice, the translation may be made in one step, but even then it may be analyzed as involving these two steps.

References

  • Anderson, E. (1993). Value in ethics and economics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cross, N. (2008). Engineering design methods. Strategies for product design (4th ed.). Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (2005). Should we pass the buck? In T. Rønnow-Rasmussen & M. J. Zimmerman (Eds.), Recent work on intrinsic value (pp. 33–44). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, M., Howe, D. C., & Nissenbaum, H. (2008). Embodying values in technology. Theory and practise. In J. Van den Hoven & J. Weckert (Eds.), Information technology and moral philosophy (pp. 322–353). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, B., & Kahn, P. H., Jr. (2003). Human values, ethics and design. In J. Jacko & A. Sears (Eds.), Handbook of human-computer interaction (pp. 1177–1201). Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, R. (1964). Animal machines; The new factory farming industry. London: Vincent Stuart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, R. (1993). Case study: Farm animals. In R. J. Berry (Ed.), Environmental dilemmas: Ethics and decisions (pp. 118–135). London: Chapman & Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keeney, R. L. (1992). Value-focused thinking: A path to creative decision making. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keeney, R. L., & Raiffa, H. (1993). Decisions with multiple objectives: Preferences and value tradeoffs. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press. (Original edition published in 1976 by Wiley)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuit, A. R., Ehlhardt, D. A., & Blokhuis, H. J. (1989). Alternative improved housing systems for poultry. Beekbergen: Ministry of Agriculture and Fisheries of the Netherlands, Directorate of Agricultural Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, H. S. (1997). Practical reasoning about final ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sclove, R. E. (1995). Democracy and technology. New York: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van de Poel, I. (1998). Why are chickens housed in battery cages? In C. Disco & B. van der Meulen (Eds.), Getting new technologies together. Studies in making sociotechnical order (pp. 143–178). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van den Hoven, J. (2007). ICT and value sensitive design. In P. Goujon, S. Lavelle, P. Duquenoy, K. Kimppa, & V. Laurent (Eds.), The information society: Innovation, legitimacy, ethics and democracy in honor of Professor Jacques Berleur S.J. (pp. 67–72). Boston: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vincenti, W. G. (1990). What engineers know and how they know it (Analytical studies from aeronautical history). Baltimore/London: The John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, M. J. (2004). Intrinsic vs. extrinsic value. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2004 ed.). Stanford: Stanford University. URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2004/entries/value-intrinsic-extrinsic/

Download references

Acknowledgments

An earlier version of this paper was presented at the Forum on Philosophy, Engineering, and Technology (fPET-2010), Colorado School of Mines, Golden, CO, USA, May 9–10, 2010. I am grateful to NIAS, the Netherlands Institute for Advanced Study, for providing me with the opportunity, as a Fellow-in-Residence, to work on this paper during my stay in the academic year 2009–2010.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ibo van de Poel .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

van de Poel, I. (2013). Translating Values into Design Requirements. In: Michelfelder, D., McCarthy, N., Goldberg, D. (eds) Philosophy and Engineering: Reflections on Practice, Principles and Process. Philosophy of Engineering and Technology, vol 15. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7762-0_20

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics