Epistemic Reasoning in Life and Literature

Chapter
Part of the Outstanding Contributions to Logic book series (OCTR, volume 3)

Abstract

Epistemic Logic has recently acquired importance as a growing field with influence in Distributed Computing, Philosophy, Economics, and of late even in Social Science and Animal behavior. Here, on a relatively light note, we give examples of epistemic reasoning occurring in literature and used very effectively by writers like Shakespeare, Shaw, Arthur Conan Doyle, and O’Henry. For variety we also give an example of epistemic reasoning used by fireflies, although it is far fetched to suppose that fireflies use epistemic reasoning in any kind of a conscious way. Surely they are getting a lot of help from Darwin. It is this writer’s hope that epistemic reasoning as a formal discipline will some day acquire importance comparable to that of Statistics. Hopefully these examples make part of the case.

Keywords

Epistemic reasoning Theory of mind Multiagent epistemology  Logic in literature Game theory in literature 

Notes

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Steven Brams, Yang Liu, Carol Parikh, Prashant Parikh, Paul Pedersen, Hilary Putnam, Noson Yanofsky and Ruili Ye for comments. This paper was supported by a grant from PSC-CUNY under the Faculty Research Assistance Program.

References

  1. Alchourron, C., Gärdenfors, P., & Makinson, D. (1985). On the logic of theory change: Partial meet contraction and revision functions. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50, 510–530.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Brams, S. (2011). Game theory and the humanities: Bridging two worlds. Cambridge: MIT press.Google Scholar
  3. Brams, S. (2003). Bibliocal games. Cambridge: MIT press.Google Scholar
  4. Chwe, M. S.-Y. (2013). Jane Austen, Game theorist. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Chwe, M. S.-Y. (2003). Rational ritual. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Wikipedia entry on Drona, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Drona.
  7. Genot, E., & Jacot, J. (2012). How can questions be informative before they are answered? Strategic information in interrogative games. Episteme, 9(2), 189–204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Grandin, T. (2006). Thinking in pictures and other reports from my life with autism. New York: Vintage Books.Google Scholar
  9. Kourousias, G., & Makinson, D. (September 2007). Parallel interpolation, splitting, and relevance in belief change. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 72, 994–1002.Google Scholar
  10. van Lambalgen, M., & Counihan, M. (2008). Formal models for real people. Journal of Logic Language and Information, 17, 385–389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Neyman, A. (1991). The positive value of information. Games and Economic Behavior, 3, 350–355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Osborne, M., & Rubinsein, A. (1994). A course in game theory. Cambridge: MIT press.Google Scholar
  13. Parikh, R. (1999). Belief revision and language splitting. In Proc. Logic, Language and Computation, Ed. Moss, Ginzburg and de Rijke, CSLI 1999, pp. 266–278 (earlier version appeared in 1996 in the prliminary proceedings).Google Scholar
  14. Parikh, R. (March 2011). Beth definability, interpolation and language splitting. Synthese, 179(2), 211–221.Google Scholar
  15. Parikh, R. (2008). Sentences, belief and logical omniscience, or what does deduction tell us? Review of Symbolic Logic, 1, 459–476.Google Scholar
  16. Parikh, R., & Ramanujam, R. (2003). Journal of Logic, Language and Information. A knowledge based semantics of messages, 12, 453–467.Google Scholar
  17. Parikh, R., Tasdemir, C., & Witzel, A. (2011). The power of knowledge in games, http://cuny.academia.edu/RohitParikh/Papers/.
  18. Premack, D. G., & Woodruff, G. (1978). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1(4).Google Scholar
  19. Sacks, O. (1995). An anthropologist on mars. New York: Vintage Books.Google Scholar
  20. Skyrms, B. (2010). Signals: Evolution, learning and information. New York: Oxford University press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Smith, J. (2009). The mahabharata : An abridged translation (p. 477). New Delhi: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  22. Verbrugge, R., & Mol, L. (2008). Learning to apply theory of mind. Journal of Logic Language and Information, 17(4), 489–511.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition, 13(1), 103–128.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Brooklyn College of the City University of New YorkNew YorkUSA
  2. 2.Graduate Center of the City University of New YorkNew YorkUSA

Personalised recommendations