Advertisement

A Role for Quasi-Empiricism in Mathematics Education

  • Eduard GlasEmail author
Chapter

Abstract

Although there are quite a few directions in modern philosophy of mathematics that invoke some essential role for (quasi-)empirical material, this chapter will be devoted exclusively to what may be considered the seminal tradition. This enabled me to present the subject as one coherent whole and to forestall the discussion getting scattered in a diversity of directions without doing justice to any one of them.

Quasi-empiricism in this tradition is the view that the logic of mathematical inquiry is based, like the logic of scientific discovery, on the bottom-up retransmission of falsity (by means of counterexamples) rather than the top-down transmission of axiomatic truth. Imre Lakatos, who originally introduced the distinction between Euclidean and quasi-empirical theories, construed mathematics as a quasi-empirical science following in essence Popper’s method of conjectures and refutations. His essay on Proofs and Refutations was an attempt to apply, and thereby to test, Popper’s critical method and fallibilist theory of knowledge in a field – mathematics – to which it had not primarily been intended to apply. While Popper’s proposal stood up gloriously to this test, the new application gave rise also to new insights, in particular the construal of proofs as thought experiments with a role similar to that of testing and corroborating experiments in science.

After examination of a number of examples of mathematical thought-experiments from this perspective, the doctrine of the relative autonomy of objective knowledge is focussed upon, a doctrine which is part and parcel of the dialectic of proofs and refutations and hence of the quasi-empiricist programme.

Some remarks on the educational implications of quasi-empiricism conclude this chapter. These implications have no direct bearing on the actual practice of teaching mathematics in the classroom, but are mainly, if not exclusively, concerned with the image of mathematics that is conveyed in education.

Keywords

Mathematical Knowledge Thought Experiment Mathematical Object Objective Knowledge Human Consciousness 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Chazan, D. (1990) ‘Quasi-Empirical Views of Mathematics and Mathematics Teaching’, Interchange 21, p. 14–23Google Scholar
  2. Corfield, D. (1997) ‘Assaying Lakatos’s Philosophy of Mathematics’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 28, p. 99–121Google Scholar
  3. Corfield, D. (1998) ‘Beyond the Methodology of Mathematics Research Programmes’, Philosophia Mathematica 6, p. 272–301Google Scholar
  4. Dijksterhuis, E.J. (1987) Archimedes, Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
  5. Drake, S. (1975) ‘Galileo’s New Science of Motion’, p. 131–156 in: Monelli, M.N.R. & Shea, W.R. (eds.) Reason, Experiment, and Mysticism in the Scientific Revolution, Science History PublicationsGoogle Scholar
  6. Glas, E. (1995) ‘Kuhn, Lakatos, and the Image of Mathematics’, Philosophia Mathematica 3, p. 225–247Google Scholar
  7. Glas, E. (1999) ‘Thought Experimentation and Mathematical Innovation’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 30, p. 1–19Google Scholar
  8. Glas, E. (2001) ‘The “Popperian Programme” and Mathematics’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 32, p. 119–137, 355–376Google Scholar
  9. Glas, E. (2006) ‘Mathematics as objective knowledge and as human practice’, in: R. Hersh (ed.), 18 Unconventional Essays on the Nature of Mathematics, Springer, p. 289–303Google Scholar
  10. Hintikka, J. & Remes, U. (1974) The Method of Analysis: its Geometrical Origin and its General Significance, ReidelGoogle Scholar
  11. Irvine, A.D. (ed.) (1990) Physicalism in Mathematics, KluwerGoogle Scholar
  12. Lakatos, I. (1963–64), ‘Proofs and Refutations’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 14, p. 1–25, 120–139, 221–245, 296–342Google Scholar
  13. Lakatos, I. (ed.) (1967) Problems in the Philosophy of Mathematics, North-HollandGoogle Scholar
  14. Lakatos, I. (1976), (Worral, J. & Zahar, E., eds.) Proofs and Refutations, the Logic of Mathematical Discovery, Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
  15. Lakatos, I. (1978a) (Worral, J. & Curry, G., eds.) The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes, Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
  16. Lakatos, I. (1978b) (Worral, J. & Curry, G., eds.) Mathematics, Science and Epistemology, Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
  17. Niiniluoto, I. (1992) ‘Reality, Truth, and Confirmation in Mathematics’, p. 60–78 in: Echeverria, J., Ibarra, A. & Mormann, T. (eds.) The Space of Mathematics, De GruyterGoogle Scholar
  18. Otte, M. & Panza, M. (eds.) (1996) Analysis and Synthesis in Mathematics: History and Philosophy, KluwerGoogle Scholar
  19. Pólya, G. (1957) How To Solve It, Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
  20. Pólya, G. (1962) Mathematical Discovery: On Understanding, Learning, and Teaching Problem Solving, 2 vols, John Wiley and SonsGoogle Scholar
  21. Pólya, G. (1968) Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning Volume II: Patterns of Plausible Inference, Princeton University Press (second edition)Google Scholar
  22. Pólya, G. (1954) Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning Volume I: Induction and Analogy in Mathematics, Princeton University Press (second edition Pólya 1973)Google Scholar
  23. Popper, K.R. (1969) Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, 3rd ed., RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
  24. Popper, K.R. (1972) The Logic of Scientific Discovery, 6th ed., HutchinsonGoogle Scholar
  25. Popper, K.R. (1981) Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach, revised ed., ClarendonGoogle Scholar
  26. Popper, K. R. (1983) Realism and the Aim of Science, ed. W. W. Bartley, Rowan and LittlefieldGoogle Scholar
  27. Popper, K.R. (1984) Auf der Suche nach einer besseren Welt, PiperGoogle Scholar

Suggested Further Reading

  1. Brown, J.R. (1999) Philosophy of Mathematics: an introduction to the world of proofs and pictures, RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
  2. Corfield, D. (2003) Towards a Philosophy of Real Mathematics, Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
  3. Ernest, P. (1997) ‘The Legacy of Lakatos: Reconceptualizing the Philosophy of Mathematics’, Philosophia Mathematica 5, p. 116–134Google Scholar
  4. François, K. & Van Bendegem, J.P. (eds.) (2007) Philosophical Dimensions in Mathematics Education, SpringerGoogle Scholar
  5. Gavroglu, K., Goudraroulis, Y. & Nicolacopoulos, P. (eds.) (1989) Imre Lakatos and Theories of Scientific Change, KluwerGoogle Scholar
  6. Hersh, R. (2006) 18 Unconventional Essays on the Nature of Mathematics, SpringerGoogle Scholar
  7. Kampis, G., Kvasz, L. & Stöltzner, M. (eds.) (2002) Appraising Lakatos: Mathematics, Methodology and the Man, KluwerGoogle Scholar
  8. Larvor, B. (1998) Lakatos: An Introduction, RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
  9. Oliveri, G. (1997) ‘Criticism and the Growth of Mathematical Knowledge’, Philosophia Mathematica 5, p. 228–259Google Scholar
  10. Oliveri, G. (2006) ‘Mathematics as a Quasi-Empirical Science’, Foundations of Science 11, p. 41–79Google Scholar
  11. Tymoczko, T. (ed.) (1986) New Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics, BirkhäuserGoogle Scholar
  12. Van Kerkhove, B. (ed.) (2009) Mathematical Practices: Essays in Philosophy and History of Mathematics, World ScientificGoogle Scholar
  13. Van Kerkhove, B. & Van Bendegem, J.P. (eds.) (2007) Perspectives on Mathematical Practices: Bringing together Philosophy of Mathematics, Sociology of Mathematics, and Mathematics Education, SpringerGoogle Scholar
  14. Zheng, Y. (1990) ‘From the Logic of Mathematical Discovery to the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 41, p. 377–399Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of MathematicsDelft University of TechnologyDelftThe Netherlands

Personalised recommendations