Skip to main content

Introduction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Modelling Norms
  • 1195 Accesses

Abstract

Some basic concepts related to social norms are explored, setting the stage for defining what social norms are and how they might be studied. Theoretical social science and agent-based modelling is examined in relation to thought experimentation.

Man is a mediocre egoist; even the most cunning thinks his habits more important than his advantage.

Friedrich Nietzsche

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See for example http://listverse.com/2008/09/07/top-10-unethical-psychological-experiments/

  2. 2.

    See Sect. 2.2.4 for a summary of the experiment.

  3. 3.

    For a full analysis of thought experiments in philosophy see Cohnitz (2006).

References

  • Brendel, E. (2004). Intuition pumps and the proper use of thought experiments. Dialectica, 58(1), 89–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R. (1991). Laboratory of the mind: Thought experiments in the natural sciences. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R. (2003). Why empiricism won’t work. Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association, 2, 271–279.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R. (2004a). Peeking into plato’s heaven. Philosophy of Science, 71, 1126–1138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R. (2004b). Why thought experiments do transcend empiricism. In C. Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in the philosophy of science (pp. 23–43). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohnitz, D. (2006). Gedankenexperimente in der philosophie. Paderborn: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1976). The selfish gene. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1984). Elbow room: The varieties of free will worth wanting. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1995). Intuition pumps. In J. Brockman (Ed.), The third culture: Beyond the scientific revolution (pp. 180–197). New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A., & Infeld, L. (1938). The evolution of physics. London: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellickson, R. C. (1998). Law and economics discovers social norms. Faculty Scholarship Series (Paper 407). http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/fss_papers/407.

  • Elsenbroich, C., & Xenitidou, M. (2012). Three kinds of normative behaviour: Minimal requirements for feedback models. Computational and Mathematical Organization Theory, 18(1), 113–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1989). Nuts and bolts for the social sciences. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fairchild, G., van Goozen, S., Stollery, S. J., Brown, J., Gardiner, J., Herbert, J., & Goodyer, I. M. (2008). Cortisol diurnal rhythm and stress reactivity in male adolescents with early-onset or adolescence-onset conduct disorder. Biological Psychology, 64(7), 599–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galileo, G. (1628/2010). Dialogues Concerning Two New Sciences. Digireads.com.

  • Geertz, C. (1973). The interpretation of cultures. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, N. (2008). Agent-based models: Number 153 in quantitative applications in the social sciences. Los Angeles: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, N., & Troitzsch, K. G. (2005). Simulation for the social scientist (2nd ed.). Maidenhead/New York: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, G. (1968). The tragedy of the commons. Science, 162(3859), 1243–1248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. (1975). The survival lottery. Philosophy, 50, 81–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P., & Swedberg, R. (1998). Social mechanisms: An analytical approach to social theory. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hollis, M. (1994). The philosophy of social science. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1752). Political discourses. In C. U. P. Knut Haakonssen (Ed.), Politicial essays (1994th ed.). Edinburgh: A. Kincaid and A. Donaldson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kühne, U. (1995). Thought experiments and the inference to a coherent explanation. In Volume of Abstracts. 10th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Florence (p. 238).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kühne, U. (2005). Die Methode des Gedankenexperimnents. Suhrkamp Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kühne, U. (2009). A short history of the method of thought experiments in science. In Thought Experiments: A Workshop, Toronto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milgram, S. (1973). The perils of obedience. Harper’s Magazine, 62–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, O. (1921). Anti-spengler. München: G.D.W. Callwey.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (2004a). On thought experiments: Is there more to the argument? Proceedings of the 2002 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. Philosophy of Science, 71, 1139–1151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (2004b). Why thought experiments do not transcend empiricism. In C. Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in the philosophy of science (pp. 44–66). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2003). Statistics and causal inference: A review. Sociedad de Estadistica e Investigacion Operativa Test, 12(2), 101–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1982). Reason, truth and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. (1971). Dynamic models of segregation. Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 1, 143–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1984). Minds, brains and science: The 1984 Reith lectures. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stöckler, M. (2000). On modeling and simulation as instruments for the study of complex systems. In M. Carrier, G. J. Massey, & L. Ruetsche (Eds.), Science at century’s end. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburg Press/Universitaetsverlag Koblenz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, J. C. (1996). Some current issues in research on social identity and self-categorization theories. In N. Ellemers, R. Spears, & B. Doosje (Eds.), Social identity. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilensky, U. (1997). NetLogo segregation model Technical report, Center for Connected Learning and Computer-Based Modeling, Northwestern University, Evanston.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Elsenbroich, C., Gilbert, N. (2014). Introduction. In: Modelling Norms. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7052-2_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics