Ancient and Medieval Theories

Chapter
Part of the Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind book series (SHPM, volume 12)

Abstract

Memory and recollection have always been important in very different areas of human experience, and this has profoundly influenced the history of these concepts. Because of this, different traditions of memory and recollection have existed throughout the history of ideas, sometimes taking parallel courses, at other times intersecting with and influencing each other. A purely philosophical tradition was shaped in particular by, and with constant reference to, Plato and Aristotle, and this tradition created different concepts to be used in the philosophy of mind and the philosophy of science. A rhetorical conception of memory was shaped in a second tradition by ideas like the ones that we find in Cicero’s works and in the Rhetoric to Herennius, but, in contrast with the other views on memory, this was not a dynamic conception, and it remained basically unaltered throughout Antiquity and the Middle Ages. Finally, an ethical tradition that treated memory as part of human prudence had many different sources of inspiration, but perhaps the most important were Plato, Cicero, Neoplatonic authors and Augustine.

Keywords

Philosophical Tradition Internal Image Ethical Tradition Platonic View Intellectual Object 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Cicero. (1994a). De inventione (G. Achard & Les Belles lettres, Ed. and Trans.). Paris: C.U.F..Google Scholar
  2. Annas, J. (1992b). Aristotle on memory and the self, in M. Nussbaum & A. Oksenberg Rorty (Eds.), 297–311.Google Scholar
  3. Anzulewicz, H., & Söder, J. R. (2004). see Albert the Great, De homine. Google Scholar
  4. Baddeley, A., Aggleton, J., & Conway, M. (Eds.). (2001). Episodic memory: New directions in research. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Barnes, J. (1993). Aristotle: Posterior analytics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  6. Black, D. (1996). Memory, individuals, and the past in Averroes’s psychology. Medieval Philosophy and Theology, 5, 161–187.Google Scholar
  7. Bloch, D. (2007). Aristotle on memory and recollection. Text, translation, interpretation, and reception in western scholasticism (Philosophia Antiqua 110). Leiden: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Blumenthal, H. J. (1971). Plotinus’ psychology. His doctrines of the embodied soul. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
  9. Burnyeat, M. F. (1990). The Theaetetus of Plato, with a translation of Theaetetus by M. J. Levett, revised by M. Burnyeat. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  10. Carruthers, M. J. (1990). The book of memory. A study of memory in medieval culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Coleman, J. (1992). Ancient and medieval memories. Studies in the reconstruction of the past. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Cox, V., & Ward, J. O. (Eds.). (2006). The rhetoric of Cicero in its medieval and early Renaissance commentary tradition (Brill’s companions to the Christian tradition 2). Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
  13. Detel, W. (1993). Aristoteles: Analytica Posteriora, in Aristoteles: Werke in deutscher Übersetzung 3.2. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag.Google Scholar
  14. Di Martino, C. (2003). Les Parva naturalia, tradition arabe, in Goulet (Ed.), 375–378.Google Scholar
  15. Di Martino, C. (2007). Memory and recollection in Ibn Sīnā’s and Ibn Rushd’s philosophical texts translated into Latin in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries: A perspective on the doctrine of the internal senses in Arabic psychological science. In H. Lagerlund (Ed.), Forming the mind: Essays on the internal senses and the mind/body problem from Avicenna to the medical enlightenment (Studies in the history of the philosophy of mind 5, pp. 16–26). Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  16. Frede, M. (1990). An empiricist view of knowledge: Memorism, in Everson (Ed.), 225–250.Google Scholar
  17. Gutas, D. (1988). Avicenna and the Aristotelian tradition. Introduction to reading Avicenna’s philosophical works. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
  18. Hasse, D. N. (2000). Avicenna’s De anima in the latin west. The formation of a peripatetic philosophy of the soul 1160–1300. London/Turin: The Warburg Institute/Aragno.Google Scholar
  19. Kahn, C. H. (1981).The role of Nous in the cognition of first principles in Posterior analytics, II.19’. In E. Berti (Ed.), Aristotle on science: The posterior analytics (pp. 385–414). Padua: Editrice Antenore.Google Scholar
  20. King, P. (2004a). Duns Scotus on mental content. In O. Boulnois et al. (Eds.), Duns Scot à Paris, 1302–2002 (Textes et etudes du Moyen Âge 26, pp. 65–88). Turnhout: Brepols.Google Scholar
  21. King, R. A. H. (2004b). Aristoteles: De Memoria et Reminiscentia, a German translation with an introduction and commentary, in Aristoteles: Werke, 14.2. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag.Google Scholar
  22. King, R. A. H. (2009). Aristotle and Plotinus on memory. Berlin: de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Lang, H. S. (1980). On memory. Aristotle’s corrections of Plato. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 18, 379–393.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Løkke, H. (2004). Early Stoic epistemology. Ph. D. dissertation, Oxford University, Oxford.Google Scholar
  25. McCumber, J. (1978). Anamnesis as memory of intelligibles in Plotinus. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 60, 160–167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. O’Daly, G. (1997). Augustine. In D. Furley (Ed.), From Aristotle to Augustine (Routledge history of philosophy, Vol. II, pp. 388–428). London/New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  27. O’Rourke Boyle, M. (1987). The prudential Augustine: The virtuous structure and sense of his confessions. Recherches Augustiniennes, 22, 129–150.Google Scholar
  28. Payer, P. J. (1979). Prudence and the principles of natural law: A medieval development. Speculum, 54, 55–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Rahman, F. (1952). see Avicenna.Google Scholar
  30. Ross, W. D. (1949). Aristotle’s prior and posterior analytics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  31. Ross, W. D. (1955). Aristotle: Parva Naturalia. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Scott, D. (1995). Recollection and experience: Plato’s theory of learning and its successors. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Scott, D. (2006). Plato’s meno. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  34. Sorabji, R. (1972/2004). Aristotle on memory (2nd ed.). London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
  35. Taske, R. (2001). Augustine’s philosophy of memory. In E. Stump & N. Kretzmann (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Augustine (pp. 148–158). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Tulving, E. (1983). Elements of episodic memory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  37. Walzer, R., & Frede, M. (1985). Galen. Three treatises on the nature of science: On the sects for beginners, an outline of empiricism, on medical experience. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  38. Warren, E. W. (1965). Memory in Plotinus. The Classical Quarterly, 15, 252–260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Wolter, A. B. (1990). The philosophical theology of John Duns Scotus, ed. M. McCord Adams (Ithaca/London: Cornell University Press)Google Scholar
  40. Wolter, A. B., & McCord Adams, M. (1993). Memory and intuition: A focal debate in fourteenth century cognitive psychology. Franciscan Studies, 53, 175–230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Saxo-InstituteUniversity of CopenhagenCopenhagenDenmark

Personalised recommendations