Skip to main content

Communicative Source of Moral Imperativity

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Ethics or Moral Philosophy

Part of the book series: Contemporary Philosophy: A New Survey ((COPH,volume 11))

  • 1164 Accesses

Abstract

The author argues that particular moral decisions and actions are determined by actual experience of human relations rather than by general principles only; moral imperativity may be presented either in the form of principles, or through agent’s immediate reactions to particular communicative situations and other persons’ expectations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It is only clear that the law of reputation is based on the divine law. However, uncertainty in Locke ’s explanation of “the divine law” and “the law of reputation” does not allow treating them definitely. Locke clarified neither the relation between duty, right, and virtue, nor between sin, wrong, and vice.

  2. 2.

    Generalized reciprocity is usually interpreted as reciprocity carried out through successive relations of individuals as members of a community. On different kinds of reciprocity see: Seaford (1998), and Tullberg (2004).

  3. 3.

    In such representation of morality one point is worth mentioning, though its entire discussion would take us out of the framework of this chapter. Oakeshott understood morality in terms of self-realization of the person as moral agent, particularly, in the second form of morality – in persons’ attitude towards ‘moral ideals’ and ‘moral rules’. However he did not explain the locus of ideals and rules he called ‘moral’ in morality or in relation to it.

  4. 4.

    For positive and negative dimensions of amour-propre see O’Hagan (1999: 171–179). It is worth adding that in its negative meaning amour-propre could be probably considered as one of the direct intellectual precursors of Friedrich Nietzsche ’s notion of ressentiment.

  5. 5.

    The Commandment of Love, even in its partial forms known from Lev. 19: 18, 33–34, is often interpreted as a peculiar expression of the Golden Rule . The difference of the Golden Rule from the Commandment of Love I tried to show in Apressyan (2002).

  6. 6.

    Nameworthy that in the Book of Tobit Ahiqar is mentioned as Tobit’s nephew and friend.

  7. 7.

    On negative and positive implications of the Golden Rule see King (1928, 1935) and Rembert (1983).

References

  • Apressyan, R. (2002). Talion and the Golden Rule: A critical analysis of associated contexts (J. E. Walker, Trans.). Russian Studies in Philosophy, 41(1), 46–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asmus, V. (1984). Filosofskoe znachenie traktata Russo o vospitanii [Philosophical implication of Rouseau’s Treatise on education]. In V. Asmus (Ed.), Istoriko-filosofskie etiudy [Essays in the history of philosophy]. Moscow: Mysl.

    Google Scholar 

  • Confucius (2007). The Analects of Confucius (B. Watson, Trans.). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gagarin, M. (1987). Morality in Homer. Classical Philology, 82(4), 285–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King, G. B. (1928). The ‘negative’ Golden Rule. The Journal of Religion, 8(2), 268–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King, G. B. (1935). The ‘negative’ Golden Rule: Additional note. The Journal of Religion, 15(1), 59–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindenberger, J. M. (1985). Ahiqar. A new translation and introduction. In J. H. Charlesworth (Ed.), The old testament pseudepigrapha (The old testament pseudepigrapha, expansions of the “old testament” and legends, wisdom and philosophical literature, prayers, psalms and odes, fragments of lost Judeo-Hellenistic works, Vol. 2). Garden City: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1894). An essay concerning human understanding: With the notes and illustrations of the author, and an analysis of his doctrine of ideas. London/New York: George Routledge & Sons Ltd./E. P. Dutton and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Hagan, T. (1999). Rousseau. London/New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oakeshott, M. (1962). The Tower of Babel. In Rationalism in politics and other essays (pp. 59–79). London/New York: Methuen/Barnes & Noble Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rembert, R. B. (1983). The Golden Rule: Two versions and two views. Journal of Moral Education, 12(2), 100–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seaford, R. (1998). Introduction. In C. Gill, N. Postlethwaite, & R. Seaford (Eds.), Reciprocity in ancient Greece (pp. 1–11). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talmud. Soncino Babylonian Talmud. London: The Soncino Press [CD-ROM].

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullberg, J. (2004). On indirect reciprocity: The distinction between reciprocity and altruism, and a comment on suicide terrorism. The American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 63(5), 1193–1212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ruben Apressyan .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Apressyan, R. (2014). Communicative Source of Moral Imperativity. In: Fløistad, G. (eds) Ethics or Moral Philosophy. Contemporary Philosophy: A New Survey, vol 11. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6895-6_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics