Skip to main content

Hybrid Logic

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Handbook of Philosophical Logic

Part of the book series: Handbook of Philosophical Logic ((HALO,volume 17))

  • 1402 Accesses

Abstract

The starting point of this chapter is the remarkable fact that proof procedures for wide classes of hybrid logics can be given in a uniform way, and moreover, this encompasses proof procedures like natural deduction and tableau systems which are suitable for actual reasoning. A focus of the chapter is such proof procedures. Axiom systems, which are not meant for actual reasoning, are only mentioned in passing. We present a relatively small selection of procedures rather than trying to be encyclopedic. This allows us to give a reasonably detailed treatment of the selected procedures. Another focus of the chapter is the origin of hybrid logic in Arthur Prior’s philosophical work.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    The chapter is composed of material adapted from the author’s book (Braüner 2011). The author wishes to acknowledge the financial support received from The Danish Natural Science Research Council as funding for the projects HyLoMOL (2004–2008) and HYLOCORE (2009–2013).

  2. 2.

    The word “actual” has here a broad meaning, not restricted to actual human reasoning. The logic does not care whether it is a human that carries out the reasoning, or the reasoning takes place in a computer, or in some other medium.

  3. 3.

    This should not be confused with the term “hybrid systems” which in the computer science community is used for systems that combine discrete and continuous features.

  4. 4.

    Considering a nominal as a symbol that refers to something is not the only way to view nominals. Two different views on nominals can be identified in the works of Arthur Prior, as is clear from the quotation below where Prior discusses the addition of nominals to a temporal version of modal logic called tense logic.

    We might …equate the instant a with a conjunction of all those propositions which would ordinarily be said to be true at that instant, or we might equate it with some proposition which would ordinarily be said to be true at that instant only, and so could serve as an index of it (Hasle et al. 2003, p. 124).

    In the second half of the sentence, the nominal a is viewed as a proposition that can serve as an index of an instant, which is clearly in line with considering a nominal as a symbol that refers to an instant. On the other hand, in the first half of the sentence, the nominal a is viewed as a description of the content of an instant. The alternative view on nominals expressed in the first half of the sentence quoted above can also be found in a number of other places in Prior’s works, for example the following.

    The essential trick is to treat the instant variables as a special sort of propositional variables, by identifying an ‘instant’ with the totality of what would ordinarily be said to be true at that instant, …(Hasle et al. 2003, p. 141).

    See the discussion of Prior’s work in Sect. 1.2 of the present handbook chapter, in particular Footnote 8 of that section. Moreover, see the discussion in Patrick Blackburn’s paper (2006), the last paragraph of page 353, including Footnote 7, and the first complete paragraph of page 362, in particular Footnote 11. Incidentally, note that the description of the content of an instant as the conjunction of all propositions true at that instant is similar to a maximal consistent set of formulas.

  5. 5.

    In fact, the paper (Blackburn and Seligman 1995) gives a result (Proposition 4.5 on p. 264) indicating that the \(\forall \) binder has a surprisingly local character when it is not accompanied by satisfaction operators or some similar machinery. Informally, this result says that the \(\forall \) binder is then insensitive to the information at points outside the submodel generated by the point of evaluation, that is, it cannot detect the truth-values of formulas at such points.

  6. 6.

    Further discussion of this point can be found in a number of places, notably the paper Blackburn (2006). This paper also discusses hybrid-logical versions of bisimulations, which give a mathematical way to illustrate the local character of the Kripke semantics. See also the paper Simons (2006) which discusses a number of logics of location involving what we here call satisfaction operators.

  7. 7.

    All results in the present handbook chapter can be generalized to cover an arbitrary, finite number of modal operators, but in the interest of simplicity, we shall stick to one modal operator unless otherwise is specified.

  8. 8.

    It appears that this criticism presupposes a view on nominals according to which a nominal is a symbol that refers to something, like a first-order variable does. As remarked in Footnote 4 in Sect. 1.1.1, there is an alternative view on nominals according to which a nominal is viewed as a description of the content of an instant. It is not clear whether the criticism applies if this alternative view on nominals is adopted.

  9. 9.

    Sylvan actually argues that it is not necessary to reduce first-order earlier-later logic (the B-series conception of time) to tense logic (the A-series conception), or vice versa. Sylvan points out that Prior regarded tense-logical postulates as being capable of giving the meaning of statements like ‘time is continuous’ and ‘time is infinite both ways’ (cf. Prior 1967, p. 74). To this Sylvan responds as follows.

    Time is an item, a theoretical object, which bears both the tensed and the temporally ordered properties which the item in question genuinely has. …

    Part of the elegance of such a simple characterization of Time is that it neatly decouples the stable sense of ‘time’ …from various vexed issues as to exactly which properties the item genuinely has (and so from what Time is ‘really’ like). Whichever it should have, under evolving or under alternative theories, the item can remain abstractly one and the same. Naturally, tight coupling remains between the item and its properties; but it is not a meaning connection, it is a theory-dependent linkage (Sylvan 1996, p. 114).

    Sylvan sees Prior’s goal to reduce the B-series talk to A-series talk as part of a more general, and in Sylvan’s view overdeveloped, reductionist inclination of analytic philosophers, which also encompasses philosophers having the converse reduction as a goal, that is, having the goal of reducing A-series to B-series (cf. Sylvan 1996, p. 112).

  10. 10.

    A variation of the \(\downarrow \) binder (called the “freeze” quantifier) was actually introduced already in 1989 in connection with real-time logics, see the paper by Alur and Henzinger (1989). See also the survey Alur and Henzinger (1992). The \(\downarrow \) binder and the freeze quantifier were discovered independently of each other.

  11. 11.

    To prove these results, the paper Blackburn and Seligman (1995) introduces a proof technique called the spy-point technique, which later has been used in many other connections.

  12. 12.

    The interpolation theorem for propositional logic says that for any valid formula ϕ → ψ there exists a formula θ containing only the common propositional symbols of ϕ and ψ such that the formulas ϕ → θ and θ → ψ are valid. Interpolation theorems for other logics are formulated in an analogous fashion.

  13. 13.

    An unexplored line of work is to find out whether interpolation can be proved in other ways, for example using proof systems like the linear reasoning systems which in Fitting (1984) are used to prove interpolation for some particular propositional and first-order modal logics.

  14. 14.

    See ten Cate (2004) for semantic characterizations of frame classes definable by pure hybrid-logical formulas.

  15. 15.

    Like frame classes definable by pure formulas, frame classes definable by geometric theories can be given a semantic characterization, see the remark at the end of Sect. 1.4.3.

  16. 16.

    This was pointed out to the author by Balder ten Cate (personal communication).

  17. 17.

    According to Prawitz’ terminology (Prawitz 1978), a natural deduction introduction rule for a connective is explicit if the connective in question is exhibited exactly once, namely in the conclusion of the rule. Thus, according to this terminology, the hybrid-logical introduction rule for the modal operator is not explicit.

  18. 18.

    This is actually a generally occurring problem (with a generally applicable solution) since the same problem crops up (and is solved in the same way) in connection with normalisation for intuitionistic hybrid logic, cf. Braüner and de Paiva (2006), and normalisation for first-order hybrid logic, cf. Braüner (2005). See also Braüner (2011). In the first case the reduction rule for the modal operator \(\diamond \), which in intuitionistic hybrid logic is primitive, not defined, might generate new maximum formulas on the form \(@_{a}\diamond e\), and in the second case, the reduction rule for the quantifier \(\forall \) might generate new maximum formulas on the form @  a E(t) where E(t), called the existence predicate, is an abbreviation for ∃y(y = t) which in turn is an abbreviation for \(\neg \forall y\neg (y = t)\).

  19. 19.

    Labelled systems have the labelling machinery at the metalevel, whereas hybrid-logical systems have machinery with similar effect at the object level. A third option is chosen in Fitting’s paper (1972b) where a curious modal-logical axiom system is given in which labelling machinery is incorporated directly into the object language itself. In that system sequences of formulas of ordinary modal logic, delimited by a distinguished symbol ∗ , are used as names for possible worlds. To be more specific, a sequence \({\ast}\diamond \phi _{1},\ldots,\diamond \phi _{n},\diamond \phi _{n+1}{\ast}\) is used as the name of a world accessible from the world named by \({\ast}\diamond \phi _{1},\ldots,\diamond \phi _{n}{\ast}\) and in which the formula ϕ n + 1 is true, if there is one. It is allowed to form object language formulas by prefixing ordinary modal-logical formulas with such sequences. Intuitively, a prefixed formula \({\ast}\diamond \phi _{1},\ldots,\diamond \phi _{n}{\ast}\psi\) says that the formula ψ is true at the world named by the prefix. Prefixed formulas can be combined using the usual connectives of classical logic.

  20. 20.

    This terminology is used in a somewhat different sense than is common: Our destructive rules preserve information in the sense that if a conclusion of a destructive rule has a model, then this model is a model for the premise of the rule as well, that is, no models are included (note that this is opposite of soundness which says that no models are excluded). In the usual sense destructive rules are rules that do not preserve information (see Fitting 1972a).

  21. 21.

    An occurrence of a satisfaction statement @  a ϕ or the negation of a satisfaction statement \(\neg @_{a}\phi\) in a tableau can be seen as a formula ϕ together with a pair consisting of the representation of a possible world (the nominal a) and the representation of a truth-value (depending on whether the satisfaction statement is negated or not). Note in this connection that in the possible worlds semantics, the semantic value assigned to a formula is a function from possible worlds to truth-values, and set-theoretically, such a function is a set of pairs of possible worlds and truth-values (called the graph of the function). Hence, the pairs of nominals and representations of truth-values associated with formulas in the tableau system can be considered representations of elements of functions constituting semantic values. Thus, the tableau rules step by step build up semantic values of the formulas involved, similar to the way in which the accessibility relation step by step is built up (there is a difference however; the accessibility relation can be any relation, but the semantic value of a formula has to be a function, that is, a relation where no element of the domain is related to more than one element of the codomain, and this is exactly what is required of an open branch in a tableau, namely that no satisfaction statement is related to more than one truth-value).

  22. 22.

    This was pointed out to the author by Jens Ulrik Hansen.

  23. 23.

    This was pointed out to the author by Thomas Bolander.

  24. 24.

    Also other criteria could be considered, one important example being interpolation, that is, the criterion that a proof system should lend itself to the calculation of interpolants, perhaps after being enhanced with further machinery, like the tableau system for first-order hybrid logic which in the paper Blackburn and Marx (2003) is used as the basis of an algorithm that calculates interpolants. See the remarks on interpolation in Sect. 1.3. Note that there are two steps: The first step is the requirement of a logic (which here is a formal language together with a semantics) that it satisfies interpolation. This might be proved semantically, independent of any proof systems. If the logic does satisfy interpolation, then the second step is the requirement of a proof system for the logic that the proof system in question can be used as the basis for calculating interpolants.

  25. 25.

    It should be mentioned that there are a number of natural deduction and Gentzen style formulations for modal logic that do not fit this categorisation well. Notable here are formulations in terms of Nuel Belnap’s display logic and Kosta Dŏsen’s higher-level sequents. However, these formulations differ considerably from Gentzen’s original natural deduction and sequent systems and they are more complicated from a technical point of view. (Although it has to be acknowledged that display sequents as well as higher-level sequents were introduced as natural generalisations of Gentzen’s notion of a sequent, intended to allow a uniform sequent-style formulation of many different logics.) An overview can be found in Wansing (1994). Also notable are modal hypersequent systems, see Avron (1996) as well as the handbook chapter Fitting (2007).

  26. 26.

    In fact, Prawitz’ systems for S4 and S5 deviate from most standard systems since his introduction rules for □ make use of “non-local” side-conditions, that is, side-conditions that do not just refer to the premises of the rules and to undischarged assumptions, but to the whole derivations of the premises.

  27. 27.

    See Braüner and de Paiva (2006) and Braüner (2005) for the cases of intuitionistic and first-order hybrid logic. In the latter case the accessibility relation as well as the quantifier domains are subject to first-order conditions expressed by geometric theories. See also Braüner (2011).

  28. 28.

    This can actually be generalized: These two features also enable the formulation of natural deduction systems for intuitionistic hybrid logics satisfying the criterias, cf. Braüner and de Paiva (2006) and Braüner (2011), but in that case the features are interpreted intuitionistically, that is, they are interpreted as statements in intuitionistic first-order logic and intuitionistic hybrid logic. See also Braüner (2006). In the case of first-order hybrid logic, cf. Braüner (2005) and Braüner (2011), we can furthermore express that an individual t exists at a world a, that is, the formula @  a E(t) is true, which enables the formulation of natural deduction systems for first-order hybrid logics satisfying the criteria (here E(t) is the existence predicate which is defined as an abbreviation for ∃y(y = t)).

  29. 29.

    In the paper (Brünnler 2006) Kai Brünnler compares labelled and unlabelled Gentzen systems for modal logic. A system of the latter kind is a system that does not use labels, which he makes more precise by calling a Gentzen system pure if each sequent has an equivalent object language formula. Clearly, what we here call standard proof systems for modal logic are pure: In natural deduction terminology, a derivation of a modal-logical formula ϕ from a set of modal-logical formulas \(\Gamma \) is equivalent to the modal-logical formula \(\bigwedge \Gamma \rightarrow \phi\). On the other hand, labelled natural deduction systems for modal logic are clearly not pure, but it is remarkable that hybrid-logical natural deduction systems actually are pure in Brünnler’s sense.

  30. 30.

    Belnap’s paper (1962) is a response to Prior’s paper (1960) in which Prior raises doubt as to whether the meaning of logical connectives can be explained in terms of derivation rules along the lines of natural deduction introduction and elimination rules. In his paper, Prior introduces a logical connective tonk with introduction rules similar to the standard natural deduction introduction rules for disjunction and elimination rules similar to the standard natural deduction elimination rules for conjunction. An effect of extending a formal system with tonk together with the mentioned rules is that any formula becomes derivable, which obviously is absurd. In his response to Prior’s paper, Belnap suggests imposing certain restrictions on derivation rules, thereby excluding Prior’s rules for tonk from the permissible rules for a connective. According to Belnap, the crucial restriction is conservativity: When a formal system is extended with a new logical connective together with a set of derivation rules, then for any formula built using only the original connectives, it is required that if the formula is derivable in the extended system, then it is also derivable in the original system, that is, it is derivable without using the derivation rules for the new connective.

  31. 31.

    A frequently discussed issue in proof-theoretic semantics is which restrictions to impose on the derivation rules for a connective, that is, which sets of derivation rules to take as permissible. This discussion can be traced back to Prior (1960) and Belnap’s (1962) papers, cf. the previous footnote. A number of restrictions on derivation rules have been proposed, one proposal being conservativity, cf. the previous footnote, another proposal being the inversion principle (cf. the paper Prawitz (1971)).

References

  • Alur, R., and T.A. Henzinger. 1989. A really temporal logic. In Proceedings of the 30th annual symposium on foundations of computer science (FOCS), 164–169. Washington, DC: IEEE Computer Society Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alur, R., and T.A. Henzinger. 1992. Logics and models of real time: A survey. In Real time: Theory in practice, volume 600 of lecture notes in computer science, ed. J.W. de Bakker, C. Huizing, W.P. de Roever, G. Rozenberg, 74–106. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Areces, C. 2000. Logic engineering. The case of description and hybrid logics. PhD thesis, Institute for Logic, Language and Computation, University of Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Areces, C., and J. Heguiabehere. 2002. HyLoRes 1.0: Direct resolution for hybrid logics. In Proceedings of the 18th international conference on automated deduction, Lecture notes in computer science, vol. 2392, ed. A. Voronkov, 156–160. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Areces, C., and B. ten Cate. 2007. Hybrid logics. In Handbook of modal logic, ed. P. Blackburn, J. van Benthem, and F. Wolter, 821–868. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Areces, C., P. Blackburn, and M. Marx. 1999. The computational complexity of hybrid temporal logics. Logic Journal of IGPL 8: 653–679.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Areces, C., P. Blackburn, and M. Marx. 2001a. Hybrid logics: Characterization, interpolation and complexity. Journal of Symbolic Logic 66: 977–1010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Areces, C., M. de Rijke, and H. de Nivelle. 2001b. Resolution in modal, description and hybrid logic. Journal of Logic and Computation 11: 717–736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Areces, C., P. Blackburn, and M. Marx. 2003. Repairing the interpolation theorem in quantified modal logic. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 124: 287–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Avron, A. 1996. The method of hypersequents in the proof theory of propositional non-classical logics. In Logic: Foundations to applications, ed. W. Hodges, M. Hyland, C. Steinhorn, and J. Truss, 1–32. Oxford: Oxford Science Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Basin, D., S. Matthews, and L. Viganò. 1997. Labelled propositional modal logics: Theory and practice. Journal of Logic and Computation 7: 685–717.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Belnap, N.D. 1962. Tonk, plonk and plink. Analysis 22: 130–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P., and M. Marx. 2003. Constructive interpolation in hybrid logic. Journal of Symbolic Logic 68: 463–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P., and J. Seligman. 1995. Hybrid languages. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 4: 251–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P., and B. ten Cate. 2006. Pure extensions, proof rules, and hybrid axiomatics. Studia Logica 84: 277–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P., and M. Tzakova. 1998. Hybridizing concept languages. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence 24: 23–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P., and M. Tzakova. 1999. Hybrid languages and temporal logic. Logic Journal of IGPL 7: 27–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P., M. de Rijke, and Y. Venema. 2001. Modal logic, Cambridge tracts in theoretical computer science, vol. 53. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P. 1993. Nominal tense logic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 14: 56–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P. 2000a. Internalizing labelled deduction. Journal of Logic and Computation 10: 137–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P. 2000b. Representation, reasoning, and relational structures: a hybrid logic manifesto. Logic Journal of IGPL 8: 339–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P. 2006. Arthur Prior and hybrid logic. Synthese 150: 329–372 (Special issue edited by T. Braüner, P. Hasle, and P. Øhrstrøm).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolander, T., and P. Blackburn. 2007. Termination for hybrid tableaus. Journal of Logic and Computation 17: 517–554.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolander, T., and P. Blackburn. 2009. Terminating tableau calculi for hybrid logics extending K. In Proceedings of methods for modalities 5, ed. C. Areces and S. Demri, Electronic notes in theoretical computer science, vol. 231, 21–39. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolander, T., and T. Braüner. 2005. Two tableau-based decision procedures for hybrid logic. In 4th Workshop “Methods for Modalities” (M4M), Informatik-Bericht Nr. 194, ed. H. Schlingloff, 79–96. Berlin: Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolander, T., and T. Braüner. 2006. Tableau-based decision procedures for hybrid logic. Journal of Logic and Computation 16: 737–763. Revised and extended version of (Bolander and Braüner, 2005).

    Google Scholar 

  • Boolos, G. 1984. Don’t eliminate cut. Journal of Philosophical Logic 13: 373–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braüner, T., and V. de Paiva. 2006. Intuitionistic hybrid logic. Journal of Applied Logic 4: 231–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braüner, T. 2002b. Modal logic, truth, and the master modality. Journal of Philosophical Logic 31: 359–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braüner, T. 2004a. Natural deduction for hybrid logic. Journal of Logic and Computation 14: 329–353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braüner, T. 2004b. Two natural deduction systems for hybrid logic: A comparison. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 13: 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braüner, T. 2005. Natural deduction for first-order hybrid logic. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 14: 173–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braüner, T. 2006. Axioms for classical, intuitionistic, and paraconsistent hybrid logic. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 15: 179–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braüner, T. 2007. Why does the proof-theory of hybrid logic work so well? Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 17: 521–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braüner, T. 2011. Hybrid logic and its proof-theory, Applied logic series, vol. 37. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broda, K., M. Finger, and A. Russo. 1999. Labelled natural deduction for substructural logics. Logic Journal of IGPL 7: 283–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brünnler, K. 2006. Deep sequent systems for modal logic. In Advances in modal logic, vol. 6, ed. G. Governatori, I. Hodkinson, and Y. Venema, 117–119. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bull, R.A. 1970. An approach to tense logic. Theoria 36: 282–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bull, R.A., and K. Segerberg. 2001. Basic modal logic. In Handbook of philosophical logic, vol. 3, 2nd ed, ed. D.M. Gabbay and F. Guenthner, 1–81. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, C.C., and H.J. Keisler. 1990. Model theory, 3rd ed. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copeland, J. (ed.). 1996. Logic and reality: Essays in the legacy of Arthur Prior. Oxford: Oxford University Press/Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copeland, J. 2007. Arthur Prior. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. Stanford: Stanford University. On-line encyclopedia article available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/prior.

  • D’Agostino, M., and M. Mondadori. 1994. The taming of the cut. Classical refutations with analytical cut. Journal of Logic and Computation 4: 285–319.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Agostino, M., D.M. Gabbay, R. Hähnle, and J. Posegga (eds.). 1999. Handbook of tableau methods. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donini, F.M., and F. Massacci. 2000. Exptime tableaux for ALC. Artificial Intelligence 124: 87–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K., and A.N. Prior. 1977. Worlds, times and selves. London: Duckworth. Based on manuscripts by Prior with a preface and a postscript by K. Fine.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M. 1972a. Tableau methods of proof for modal logics. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 13: 237–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M. 1972b. \(\varepsilon\)-calculus based axiom systems for some propositional modal logics. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 13: 381–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M. 1983. Proof methods for modal and intuitionistic logic. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M. 1984. Linear reasoning in modal logic. Journal of Symbolic Logic 49: 1363–1378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M. 1992a. Many-valued modal logics. Fundamenta Informaticae 15: 235–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M. 1992b. Many-valued modal logics II. Fundamenta Informaticae 17: 55–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M. 1995. Tableaus for many-valued modal logic. Studia Logica 55: 63–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M. 2007. Modal proof theory. In Handbook of modal logic, ed. P. Blackburn, J. van Benthem, and F. Wolter, 85–138. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Franceschet, M., and M. de Rijke. 2006. Model checking hybrid logics (with an application to semistructured data). Journal of Applied Logic 4: 279–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay, D.M. 1996. Labelled deductive systems. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay, D.M., and G. Malod. 2002. Naming worlds in modal and temporal logic. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 11: 29–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galton, A. 2006. Operators vs. arguments: The ins and outs of reification. Synthese 150: 415–441 (Special issue edited by T. Braüner, P. Hasle, and P. Øhrstrøm).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gargov, G., and V. Goranko. 1993. Modal logic with names. Journal of Philosophical Logic 22: 607–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gentzen, G. 1969. Investigations into logical deduction. In The collected papers of Gerhard Gentzen, ed. M.E. Szabo, 68–131. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goranko, V. 1994. Temporal logic with reference pointers. In Proceedings of the 1st international conference on temporal logic Lecture notes in artificial intelligence, vol. 827, 133–148. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goranko, V. 1996. Hierarchies of modal and temporal logics with reference pointers. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 5: 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goranko, V. 2000. Sorting and hybrid modal logics. Manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goré, R. 1999. Chapter 6: Tableau methods for modal and temporal logics. In Handbook of tableau methods, ed. M. D’Agostino, D. Gabbay, R. Haehnle, and J. Posegga, 297–396. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, J.U. 2007. A tableau system for a first-order hybrid logic. In Proceedings of the international workshop on hybrid logic 2007, ed. J. Villadsen, T. Bolander, and T. Braüner, 32–40. 19th European Summerschool in Logic, Language and Information. Trinity College: Dublin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, J.U. 2010. Terminating tableaux for dynamic epistemic logics. In Proceedings of the 6th workshop on methods for modalities (M4M-6 2009), Electronic notes in theoretical computer science, vol. 262, ed. T. Bolander and T. Braüner, 141–156. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, J.U., T. Bolander, and T. Braüner. 2008. Many-valued hybrid logic. In Advances in modal logic, vol. 7, ed. C. Areces and R. Goldblatt, 111–132. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardt, M., and G. Smolka. 2007. Higher-order syntax and saturation algorithms for hybrid logic. In Proceedings of the international workshop on hybrid logic 2006, Electronic notes in theoretical computer science, vol. 174, ed. P. Blackburn, T. Bolander, T. Braüner, V. de Paiva, and J. Villadsen, 15–27. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasle, P., P. Øhrstrøm, T. Braüner, and J. Copeland. 2003. Revised and expanded edition of Arthur N. Prior: Papers on time and tense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. 1955. Form and content in quantification theory. Acta Philosophica Fennica 8: 8–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. 1988. On the development of the model-theoretic viewpoint in logical theory. Synthese 77: 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horrocks, I., and U. Sattler. 2005. A tableaux decision procedure for \(\mathcal{S}\mathcal{H}\mathcal{O}\mathcal{I}\mathcal{Q}\). In Proceedings of the 19th international joint conference on artificial intelligence (IJCAI 2005), ed. L.P. Kaelbling and A. Saffiotti, 448–453.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horrocks, I., U. Hustadt, U. Sattler, and R. Schmidt. 2007. Computational modal logic. In Handbook of modal logic, ed. P. Blackburn, J. van Benthem, and F. Wolter, 181–245. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, G.E., and M.J. Cresswell. 1968. An introduction to modal logic. York: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaminski, M., and G. Smolka. 2007. Hybrid tableaux for the difference modality. In Workshop Proceedings of methods for modalities 5, ed. Carlos Areces and Stéphane Demri, 269–284. Paris: École Normale Supérieure de Cachan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaminski, M., and G. Smolka. 2009. Terminating tableau systems for hybrid logic with difference and converse. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 18: 437–464 (Special issue edited by T. Braüner and T. Bolander).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, A.J.P. 1970. Arthur Norman Prior (1914–1969). Proceedings of the British Academy LVI: 321–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. 2009. Model checking for hybrid logic. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 18: 465–491 (Special issue edited by T. Braüner and T. Bolander).

    Google Scholar 

  • Massacci, F. 2000. Single step tableaux for modal logics. Journal of Automated Reasoning 24: 319–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayer, M.C., and S. Cerrito. 2010. Nominal substitution at work with the global and converse modalities. Nominal substitution at work with the global and converse modalities. In Advances in modal logic, vol. 8, ed. L. Beklemishev, V. Goranko, and V. Shehtman, 57–74. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • McTaggart, J.M.E. 1908. The unreality of time. Mind 187: 457–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, T. 2007. Prior’s tense-logical universalism. Logique et Analyse 50: 223–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Øhrstrøm, P., and P. Hasle. 1993. A.N. Prior’s rediscovery of tense logic. Erkenntnis 39: 23–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Øhrstrøm, P., and P. Hasle. 1995. Temporal logic: From ancient ideas to artificial intelligence. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Øhrstrøm, P., and P. Hasle. 2005a. A.N. Prior’s logic. In Logic and the modalities in the twentieth century, The handbook of the history of logic, vol. 6, ed. D.M. Gabbay and J. Woods. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Øhrstrøm, P., and P. Hasle. 2005b. Modern temporal logic: The philosophical background. In Logic and the modalities in the twentieth century, The handbook of the history of logic, vol. 6, ed. D.M. Gabbay and J. Woods. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Passy, S., and T. Tinchev. 1985. Quantifiers in combinatory PDL: Completeness, definability, incompleteness. In Fundamentals of computation theory FCT 85, Lecture notes in computer science, vol. 199, 512–519. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Passy, S., and T. Tinchev. 1991. An essay in combinatory dynamic logic. Information and Computation 93: 263–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prawitz, D. 1965. Natural deduction: A proof-theoretical study. Stockholm: Almqvist and Wiksell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prawitz, D. 1971. Ideas and results in proof theory. In Proceedings of the second Scandinavian logic symposium, Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, vol. 63, ed. J.E. Fenstad, 235–307. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prawitz, D. 1978. Proofs and the meaning and completeness of the logical constants. In Essays on mathematical and philosophical logic, Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, ed. J. Hintikka et al., 25–40. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A.N. 1960. The runabout inference-ticket. Analysis 21: 38–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A.N. 1967. Past, present and future. Oxford: Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A.N. 1968. Papers on time and tense. Oxford: Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A.N. 1996. Some free thinking about time. In Logic and reality: Essays in the legacy of Arthur Prior, ed. J. Copeland. Oxford: Oxford University Press/Clarendon Press (With introduction by P. Øhrstrøm in which the original dating is discussed, 43–44 and 47–51).

    Google Scholar 

  • Seligman, J. 1997. The logic of correct description. In Advances in intensional logic, Applied logic series, ed. M. de Rijke, vol. 7, 107–135. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seligman, J. 2001. Internalisation: The case of hybrid logics. Journal of Logic and Computation 11: 671–689 (Special Issue on Hybrid Logics. C. Areces and P. Blackburn (eds.)).

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, P. 2006. The logic of location. Synthese 150: 443–458 (Special issue edited by T. Braüner, P. Hasle, and P. Øhrstrøm).

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, A. 1994. The proof theory and semantics of intuitionistic modal logic. PhD thesis, University of Edinburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sustretov, D. 2009. Hybrid logics of separation axioms. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 18: 541–558 (Special issue edited by T. Braüner and T. Bolander).

    Google Scholar 

  • Sylvan, R. 1996. Other withered stumps of time. In Logic and reality: Essays in the legacy of Arthur Prior, ed. J. Copeland, 111–130. Oxford: Oxford University Press/Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ten Cate, B. 2004. Model theory for extended modal languages. PhD thesis, Institute for Logic, Language and Computation, University of Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • ten Cate, B., and T. Litak. 2007. Topological perspective on the hybrid proof rules. In Proceedings of the international workshop on hybrid logic 2006, Electronic notes in theoretical computer science, vol. 174, ed. P. Blackburn, T. Bolander, T. Braüner, V. de Paiva, and J. Villadsen, 79–94. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Troelstra, A.S., and H. Schwichtenberg. 1996. Basic proof theory, Cambridge tracts in theoretical computer science, vol. 43. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tzakova, M. 1999. Tableaux calculi for hybrid logics. In Automated reasoning with analytic tableaux and related methods (TABLEAUX 1999), Lecture notes in artificial intelligence, vol. 1617, ed. N.V. Murray, 278–292. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Benthem, J. 1983. Modal logic and classical logic. Napoli: Bibliopolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vickers, S. 1988. Topology via logic, volume 5 of Cambridge tracts in theoretical computer science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Viganò, L. 2000. Labelled non-classical logics. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wansing, H. 1994. Sequent calculi for normal modal propositional logics. Journal of Logic and Computation 4: 125–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wansing, H. 2000. The idea of a proof-theoretic semantics and the meaning of the logical operations. Studia Logica 64: 3–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Torben Braüner .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Braüner, T. (2014). Hybrid Logic. In: Gabbay, D., Guenthner, F. (eds) Handbook of Philosophical Logic. Handbook of Philosophical Logic, vol 17. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6600-6_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics