Skip to main content

My Mind Is Mine!? Cognitive Liberty as a Legal Concept

Part of the Trends in Augmentation of Human Performance book series (TAHP,volume 1)

Abstract

This chapter explores some of the legal issues raised by mind-interventions outside of therapeutic contexts. It is argued that the law will have to recognize a basic human right: cognitive liberty or mental self-determination which guarantees an individual’s sovereignty over her mind and entails the permission to both use and refuse neuroenhancements. Not only proponents but also critics of enhancements should embrace this right as they often ground their cases against enhancement on precisely the interests it protects, even though critics do not always seem to be aware of this. The contours and limits of cognitive liberty are sketched, indicating which reasons are good (or bad) grounds for political regulations of neurotechnologies.

Keywords

  • Neuroenhancement
  • Cognitive liberty
  • Law
  • Human rights
  • Political regulations

This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Art. 1 European Charter of Fundamental Rights (ECFR); Art. 1 I German Constitution; Art. 3 European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR).

  2. 2.

    Some peculiarities of legal provisions concerning the body should be noted. Feminists point to the fact that as soon as social interests are at stake, the uniquely personal body becomes highly political, e.g. restrictions on abortion, prostitution, organ selling, surrogate motherhood (cf. Fabre 2006). These limits to self-determination are probably best understood as (arguably too restrictive) dignity-based attempts to not commodify the most intimate aspects of persons.

  3. 3.

    See the European Courts of Human Rights (ECtHR) recent decision allowing crucifixes in Italian Schools (Lautsi v. Italy; App. 30814/06) compared to the ban by the German Constitutional Court (BVerfGE Vol. 93, 1).

  4. 4.

    As national legal systems differ, the following remarks are rather general legal observations.

  5. 5.

    To include non-conscious humans such as nascituri, requirements may be lowered to potentiality for mental processes. Also, acceptance of corporate legal personhood does not necessarily refute the above claim, but I must leave this issue aside here.

  6. 6.

    See the Journal of Cognitive Liberties at http://www.cognitiveliberty.org, particularly “On Cognitive Liberty I–IV”, to which this chapter is indebted.

  7. 7.

    Interestingly, “On Liberty” was written during a time in which alcohol was prohibited in some parts of the UK and the US (1859, 151; Boire 2003). Alcohol, the most widespread (social and communicative) enhancer illustrates that persons have always had an interest in changing their minds, and despite all the problems it causes, a new prohibition is unthinkable in the western world.

  8. 8.

    Art. 9 ECHR; Art. 10 ECFR, Art. 18 Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR).

  9. 9.

    The US Supreme Court apparently referred to freedom of thought in some decision, yet it is not recognized as part of the 1st amendment protection in the US (cf. Blitz 2010).

  10. 10.

    ECtHR: Kokkinakis v. Greece (App. 14307/88), 25.05.1993, § 31; Decisions of the German Constitutional Court (BVerfGE) Vol. 80, 367 (381 – dissenting vote).

  11. 11.

    E.g. UN General Comment No. 22, 1993: Art. 18 UDHR does “not permit any violation whatsoever on the freedom of thought.”

  12. 12.

    I have yet to find one European case in which freedom of thought played a decisive role.

  13. 13.

    ECtHR: X v. Iceland (App. 6825/75), 1976.

  14. 14.

    Decisions of the German Constitutional Court (BVerfGE) Vol. 90, 145.

  15. 15.

    These are two well-known German cases invoking constitutional protection for trivial activities (BVerfGE Vol. 54, 143; Vol. 80, 137).

  16. 16.

    Of course, states can regulate markets to avoid exploitation of patients, secure good-practices, assess risk-benefits, etc., but they cannot, in my view, outlaw effective therapies. Therefore, the ideologically motivated ban on the use of psychedelics in (psycho-)therapy has to be lifted, provided substances are effective and relatively safe (currently, the first LSD study for more than 30 year. is conducted by Gassner, www.maps.org/research; regarding MDMA see Mithoefer et al. 2011).

  17. 17.

    A right to mental self-determination does not rely on a particular view on the mind-brain relationship. While dualists won’t object to mind-brain distinctions, reductionists may agree with the protection of physical processes as identified by their (reducible) mental properties. All that needs to be accepted is that protection of mind- (or brain-)states cannot follow the same normative rules as the protection of the integrity of other parts of the body. Unlike the latter, the mind (and its correlative neuronal processes) is highly dynamic; negative changes in mental phenomena are hardly describable as detrimental on the physical level. An analogy might be drawn to data-protecting provisions. Erasing a computer’s hard disk does not damage the disk itself but the (supervening) information, and hence, stand-alone data-protecting provisions are needed.

  18. 18.

    Whether (and to which extent) enhancements raise the “standards of reasonable care” is currently being discussed (Vincent 2012; Chap. 21 by Danaher, this volume). As standards of care are not empirical facts but normative judgments, they have to observe the right to cognitive liberty. Regularly, CL should prohibit stipulating legal expectations that others (e.g. pilots) take NE in order to discharge their duties (at least, without consent). Greater factual powers do not automatically lead to greater normative responsibilities. Exceptions might apply in severe, life-threatening circumstances (e.g. military).

  19. 19.

    For the sake of argument, it is assumed that fundamental rights apply not only to the state-citizen, but also the citizen-citizen relationship. Positive and negative liberties in this sense do not precisely match Isaiah Berlin’s famous distinction.

  20. 20.

    For an introduction to a theory of rights see Thomson (1990).

  21. 21.

    Concededly, there may be imperfect duties, i.e. duties without correlating rights, e.g. those owed to children, animals or future generations. However, the latter are arguably moral duties only, and children can be considered as fully right-bearing persons with their legal guardian(s) exercising their rights on their behalf.

  22. 22.

    As always, exceptions apply in special normative relations, e.g. parents-children.

  23. 23.

    Blitz (2010) puts forward a different claim. Drawing on the extended mind thesis by Clark and Chalmers, he proposes that the protection of freedom of thought should be expanded to “activity that is […] the functional equivalent of thought” and therewith to computers, IPhones and other devices. However, this expansion eliminates the distinction between personality and property rights. While technical devices/data-storage need (and in fact, enjoy) legal protection, their protection is based on property rights. Even though machines might be functionally similar, freedom of thought can only be meaningfully construed in relation to the human mental realm.

  24. 24.

    Cf. § 136a StPO (German Criminal Procedure Act).

References

  • Alexy R (2003) Constitutional rights, balancing and rationality. Ratio Juris 16:131–140

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Basl J (2010) State neutrality and the ethics of human enhancement technologies. AJOB Neurosci 2:41

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Blitz MJ (2010) Freedom of thought for the extended mind. Cognitive enhancement and the constitution. Wisc Law Rev 2010:1049–1118

    Google Scholar 

  • Boire RG (2000) On cognitive liberty, part I. J Cogn Lib 1:7–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Boire RG (2003) On cognitive liberty, part IV. Mill and the liberty of inebriation. J Cogn Lib 4:15–23 (www.cognitiveliberty.org)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bostrom N, Roache R (2011) Smart policy: cognitive enhancement and the public interest. In: Savulescu J, ter Meulen R, Kahane G (eds) Enhancing human capacities. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bublitz JC (2010) Doping-Kontrollen im Staatsexamen? Leistungssteigernde Stimulantien und Chancengleichheit in Prüfungen. ZJS 3/2010, 306–317

    Google Scholar 

  • Bublitz JC, Merkel R (2009) Autonomy and authenticity of enhanced personality traits. Bioethics 7:360–374

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Bublitz JC, Merkel R (2012) Crimes against minds. Crim Law Philos (forthcoming). DOI: 10.1007/s11572-012-9172-y

    Google Scholar 

  • Dees R (2010) Rawlsian “neutrality” and enhancement technologies. AJOB Neurosci 2:54

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas T (2008) Moral enhancement. J Appl Philos 25:228–245

    CrossRef  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Dresler M, Sandberg A, Ohla K, Bublitz JC, Trenado C, Mrozko-Wasowics A, Kühn S, Repantis D (2013) Non-pharmacological cognitive enhancement. J Neuropharmacol 1/2013, 64:529–543

    Google Scholar 

  • Fabre C (2006) Whose body is it anyway: justice and the integrity of the person. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Farah MJ, Illes J, Cook-Deegan R, Gardner H, Kandel E, King P, Parens E, Sahakian B, Wolpe P (2004) Neurocognitive enhancement: what can we do and what should we do? Nat Rev Neurosci 5:421–425

    CrossRef  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Feenberg A (2002) Transforming technology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Kosfeld M, Heinrichs M, Zak P, Fischbacher U (2005) Oxytocin increases trust in humans. Nature 435:673–676

    CrossRef  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg J (1986) Harm to self. Moral limits of criminal law, vol 3. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Franck G (2005) Mentaler Kapitalismus. Hanser, Munich

    Google Scholar 

  • Galert T, Bublitz JC, Heuser I, Merkel R, Repantis D, Schöne-Seifert B, Talbot D (2009) Memorandum: Das optimierte Gehirn. Gehirn Geist 10:40–48

    Google Scholar 

  • Greely H, Campbell P, Sahakian B, Harris J, Kessler RC, Gazzaniga M, Farah MJ (2008) Towards responsible use of cognitive-enhancing drugs by the healthy. Nature 456:702–705

    CrossRef  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Grey B (2011) Neuroscience and emotional harm in tort law: rethinking the American approach to free-standing emotional distress claims. In: Freeman M (ed) Law and neuroscience. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Halliburton C (2007) Letting Katz out of the bag: cognitive freedom and fourth amendment fidelity. Hastings Cent Law Rep 59:309–368

    Google Scholar 

  • Harel A (2004) Theories of rights. In: Golding M, Edmundson W (eds) Blackwell guide to the philosophy of law and legal theory. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hess E, Jokeit H (2009) Neurocapitalism. Orig. German in: Der Merkur 6/2009; engl. transl. www.eurozine.com/articles/2009-11-24-jokeit-en.html

  • Höfling W (2006) Kommentar zu Art. 3 EU-GRCH. In: Tettinger P, Stern K (eds) Kölner Gemeinschaftskommentar zur EU-GRCH. Beck, Munich

    Google Scholar 

  • Hommel T (2010) Psychisch bedingte Fehlzeiten um 40 Prozent gestiegen. Ärzte Zeitung 20.07.2010

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoppe C (2009) Neuro-Enhancement: Kein Verbot, aber bitte auch keine Empfehlungen. http://www.brainlogs.de/blogs/blog/wirklichkeit/2009-10-09/neuro-enhancement-kein-verbot-aber-bitte-auch-keine-empfehlung. Accessed 17 Feb 2013

  • Husak D (1989) Recreational drugs and paternalism. Law Philos 8:353–381

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Huxley A (1932) Brave new world. Chatto & Windus, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley A (1962) Island. Chatto & Windus, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1797) Metaphysik der Sitten. Academy Edition: Metaphysics of Morals (trans: Gregor M (1991)), vol 6. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kersting W (2007) Wohlgeordnete Freiheit. Immanuel Kants Rechts- und Staatsphilosophie. Mentis, Paderborn

    Google Scholar 

  • Kipke R (2010) Was ist so anders am Neuroenhancement? Pharmakologische und mentale Selbstveränderung im ethischen Vergleich. Jahrbuch für Wissenschaft und Ethik 15:69–99

    Google Scholar 

  • Klaming L, Vedder A (2010) Human enhancement for the common good – using neurotechnologies to improve eyewitness memory. AJOB Neurosci 3:22–33

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolber A (2006) Therapeutic forgetting: the ethical and legal implications of memory dampening. Vanderbilt Law Rev 59:1561–1626

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy N (2007) Neuroethics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Marshall J (2009) Personal freedom through human rights law? Autonomy, identity and integrity under the European convention on human rights. Martinus Nijhoff, Leiden

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Merkel R (2007) Treatment – prevention – enhancement: normative foundations and limits. In: Merkel R, Boer G, Fegert J, Galert T, Hartmann D, Nuttin B, Rosahl S (eds) Intervening in the brain – changing psyche and society. Springer, Berlin, pp 285–378

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger T (2003) Being no one. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger T (2009) Ego tunnel. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS (1859) On liberty. In: Bromwich D, Kateb G (eds) (2003) edn. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Mithoefer M, Mithoefer T, Wagner M, Jerome L, Doblin R (2011) The safety and efficacy of ±3,4-methylenedioxymethamphetamine-assisted psychotherapy in subjects with chronic, treatment-resistant posttraumatic stress disorder: the first randomized controlled pilot study. J Psychopharmacol 4:439–452

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Parens E (2005) Authenticity and ambivalence: toward understanding the enhancement debate. Hastings Cent Rep 3:34–41

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Persson I, Savulescu J (2011) Unfit for the future? Human nature, scientific progress, and the need for moral enhancement. In: Savulescu J, ter Meulen R, Kahane G (eds) Enhancing human capacities. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit P, Smith M (1996) Freedom of belief and desire. J Philos 9:429–449

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • President’s Council on Bioethics (2003) Beyond therapy. Biotechnology and the pursuit of happiness. President’s Council on Bioethics, Washington, DC

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (2005) Political liberalism. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Repantis D, Laisney O, Heuser I (2010a) Acetylcholinesterase inhibitors and memantine for neuroenhancement in healthy individuals: a systematic review. J Pharmacol Res 61:473–480

    CrossRef  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Repantis D, Laisney O, Heuser I (2010b) Modafinil and methylphenidate for neuroenhancement in healthy individuals: a systematic review. J Pharmacol Res 62:187–206

    CrossRef  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Ripstein A (2009) Force and freedom. Kant’s legal and political philosophy. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Robeyns I (2011) The capability approach. In: Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (www.sep.org)

  • Rosa H, Scheuerman W (2009) High-speed society. Social acceleration, power and modernity. Pennsylvania State University Press, University Park

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandberg A, Savulescu J (2011) The social and economic impacts of cognitive enhancements. In: Savulescu J, ter Meulen R, Kahane G (eds) Enhancing human capacities. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel M (2007) The case against perfection: ethics in the age of genetic engineering. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu J (2006) Justice, fairness and enhancement. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1093:321–338

    CrossRef  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Schermer M (2007) Brave new world versus Island – Utopian and dystopian views on psychopharmacology. Med Health Care Philos 10:119–128

    CrossRef  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Sententia W (2004) Cognitive liberty and converging technologies for improving human cognition. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1013:221–228

    CrossRef  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor K (2004) Brainwashing. The science of thought control. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson JJ (1990) The realm of rights. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Tovino SA (2007) Functional neuroimaging and the law. AJOB-Neurosci 9:44–56

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermeulen B (2006) Commentary on art. 9. In: van Dijk P, van Hoof F, van Rijn A, Zack L (eds) Theory and practice of the European convention on human rights, 4th edn. Intersentia, Antwerpen

    Google Scholar 

  • Vincent N (2012) Enhancing responsibility. In: Vincent N (ed) Legal responsibility and neuroscience. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • von der Pfordten D (2007) Kants Rechtsbegriff. Kant-Studien 98:431–442

    Google Scholar 

  • von Hirsch A (2008) Direct paternalism: criminalizing self-injurious conduct. Crim Justice Ethics 1:25–33

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jan-Christoph Bublitz .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and Permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bublitz, JC. (2013). My Mind Is Mine!? Cognitive Liberty as a Legal Concept. In: Hildt, E., Franke, A. (eds) Cognitive Enhancement. Trends in Augmentation of Human Performance, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6253-4_19

Download citation