Ten Theses on Coherence in Law

Chapter
Part of the Law and Philosophy Library book series (LAPS, volume 107)

Abstract

The aim of this chapter is to advance the following theses: (1) The concept of coherence in law may be best understood in terms of constraint satisfaction; (2) Coherence-based inference is an explanatory kind of inference; (3) There are three main operations whereby coherence may be built in the course of legal decision-making: subtraction, addition, and re-interpretation; (4) Epistemic responsibility is a pivotal component in a theory of legal coherence; (5) Coherentist standards of legal justification vary with context; (6) Coherence-based legal reasoning is a variety of reasoning about ends; (7) There are three main reasons why coherence is a value worth pursuing in law: epistemic reasons, practical reasons, and constitutive reasons; (8) The main motivation of legal coherentism is to provide a non-skeptical alternative to formalism; (9) The coherence theory of legal justification is psychologically plausible and this provides an argument in favor of this theory; (10) Legal coherentism is an agent-centered theory of justification.

Keywords

Constraint Satisfaction Legal Reasoning Epistemic Justification Virtue Epistemology Coherence Theory 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Aarnio, A., et al. 1998. On coherence theory in law. Lund: Juristfölager i Lund.Google Scholar
  2. Alexy, R., and A. Peczenik. 1990. The concept of coherence and its significance for discourse rationality. Ratio Iuris 3(1): 130–147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Amaya, A. 2007. Formal models of coherence and legal epistemology. Artificial Intelligence and Law 15: 429–447.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Amaya, A. 2008. Justificacion, coherence, and epistemic responsibility in legal fact-finding. Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology 5: 306–319.Google Scholar
  5. Amaya, A. 2009. Inference to the best legal explanation. In Legal evidence and proof: Statistics, stories, logic, ed. H. Kaptein, H. Prakken, and B. Veheij. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  6. Amaya, A. 2011. Diez tesis acerca de la coherencia en el Derecho. Discusiones 10: 21–64.Google Scholar
  7. Amaya, A. (forthcoming). The tapestry of reason: An inquiry into the nature of coherence and its role in legal argument. Oxford: Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
  8. Annis, D.B. 1978. A contextualist theory of epistemic justification. American Philosophical Quarterly 15: 213–219.Google Scholar
  9. Atienza, M. 2006. El derecho como argumentación. Barcelona: Ariel.Google Scholar
  10. Balkin, J.M. 1993. Understanding legal understanding: The legal subject and the problem of legal coherence. The Yale Law Journal 103: 105–176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. BonJour, L. 1985. The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Bratman, M.E. 1987. Intentions, plans, and practical reasoning. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Brown, G., and G. Yule. 1983. Discourse analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Cohen, S. 1986. Knowledge and context. The Journal of Philosophy 83: 574–583.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Conte, M.E. 1988. Condizioni di coerenza: Ricerche di linguistica testuale. Firenze: La Nuova Italia.Google Scholar
  16. Davidson, D. 2001. A coherence theory of truth and knowledge. In Subjective, intersubjective, objective, ed. D. Davidson. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. DePaul, M. 1993. Balance and refinement. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  18. DeRose, K. 1999. Contextualism: An explanation and defense. In The Blackwell guide of epistemology, ed. J. Greco and E. Sosa. Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  19. Doris, J.M. (ed.). 2010. The moral psychology handbook. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s empire. London: Fontana.Google Scholar
  21. Feldman, R. 2002. Epistemological duties. In The Oxford handbook of epistemology, ed. P. Moser. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Fodor, J., and E. Lepore. 1992. Holism: A shopper’s guide. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  23. Fogelin, R. 2003. Walking the tightrope of reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Gärdenfors, P. 1988. Knowledge in flux. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  25. Godfrey-Smith, P. 2003. Theory and reality: An introduction to the philosophy of science. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Goldman, A.H. 1988. Moral knowledge. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  27. Hage, J.C. 2004. Law and coherence. Ratio Iuris 17: 87–105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Hastie, R., and N. Pennington. 1991. A cognitive theory of juror decision-making: The story model. Cardozo Law Review 13: 519–557.Google Scholar
  29. Hellman, C. 1995. The notion of coherence in discourse. In Focus and coherence in discourse processing, ed. G. Rickheit and C. Habel. Berlin: DeGruyter.Google Scholar
  30. Hurley, S. 1989. Natural reasons: Personality and polity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  31. Kennedy, D. 1997. A critique of adjudication (fin de siècle). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Klein, P., and T.A. Warfield. 1994. What price coherence? Analysis 54: 129–132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Kolnai, A. 2001. Deliberation is of ends. In Varieties of practical inference, ed. E. Millgram. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  34. Kornblith, H. (ed.). 1994. Naturalizing epistemology. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  35. Lehrer, K. 2000. Theory of knowledge, 2nd ed. Boulder: Wesview Press.Google Scholar
  36. Leiter, B. 1998. Naturalism and naturalized jurisprudence. In Analyzing law: New essays in legal theory, ed. B. Bix. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  37. Lewis, D. 1996. Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 549–567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Lipton, O. 2004. Inference to the best explanation, 2nd ed. London/New York: Routledge. 1st edn. 1991.Google Scholar
  39. MacCormick, N. 1984. Coherence in legal justification. In Theorie der normen, ed. W. Krawietz et al. Berlin: Duncker and Humblot.Google Scholar
  40. Margolis, J. 1984. The locus of coherence. Linguistics and Philosophy 7(1): 3–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Millgram, E. 2001. Practical reasoning: The current state at play. In Varieties of practical inference, ed. E. Millgram. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  42. Moral, L. 2003. A modest notion of coherence in legal reasoning: A model for the European court of justice. Ratio Iuris 16(3): 296–323.Google Scholar
  43. Moravcsik, J.M.E. 1990. Thought and language. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  44. Olsson, E. 1998. Making beliefs coherent. Journal of Logic, Language, and Information 7: 143–163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Peczenik, A. 1989. On law and reason. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  46. Pryor, J. 2001. Highlights of recent epistemology. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 52: 95–124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Putnam, H. 1985. Reason, truth, and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  48. Rawls, J. 1999. A theory of justice, ed. rev., Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  49. Raz, J. 1992. The relevance of coherence. Boston University Law Review 72: 273–321.Google Scholar
  50. Richardson, H. 1994. Practical reasoning about final ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Simon, D. 1998. A psychological model of judicial decision making. Rutgers Law Journal 30(1): 1–142.Google Scholar
  52. Simon, D. 2004. A third view of the black box: Cognitive coherence in legal decision-making. The University of Chicago Law Review 71: 511–586.Google Scholar
  53. Simon et al. 2001. The emergence of coherence over the course of decision-making. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 27(5): 1250–1260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (ed.) (2007-8). Moral Psychology. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  55. Sperber, D., and D. Wilson. 1986. Relevance: Communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  56. Stein, E. 1996. Without good reason: The rationality debate in philosophy and cognitive science. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  57. Thagard, P. 1998. Ethical coherence. Philosophical Psychology 11: 405–422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Thagard, P. 2000. Coherence in thought and action. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  59. Thagard, P. 2007. Coherence, truth, and the development of scientific knowledge. Philosophy of Science 74: 28–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Thagard, P., and E. Millgram. 1996. Deliberative coherence. Synthese 108(1): 63–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Timmons, M. 1999. Morality without foundations: A defense of ethical contextualism. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  62. Wagenaar, W.A., P.J. Van Koppen, and H.F.M. Crombag. 1993. Anchored narratives: The psychology of criminal evidence. New York: St. Martin’s Press.Google Scholar
  63. Wiggins, D. 2001. Deliberation and practical reasoning. In Varieties of practical inference, ed. E. Millgram. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  64. Williams, M. 2001. Problems of knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  65. Zagzebski, L. 1996. Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht. 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institute for Philosophical ResearchNational Autonomous University of MexicoCoyocanMexico

Personalised recommendations