Skip to main content

Aristotelian Ethics and Aristotelian Rhetoric

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice ((IUSGENT,volume 23))

Abstract

In our search for an appropriate assessment of the place of rhetoric in courts, we see that the history of philosophy offers a variety of descriptions of what rhetoric is as well as a variety of notions of what rhetoric should be. The paper shows that in the work of Aristotle rhetoric and ethics are inextricably connected. Aristotle’s limitation of rhetorical activity to three domains, his description of rhetoric as an offshoot from politics, his view on emotions and his elaboration of rhetoric as ‘technê’ all imply that the art of rhetoric is directly related to the orientation towards the good life. Subsequently the paper shows that Nicomachean Ethics has a rhetorical calibre. The contingent character of practical truth implies that discovering and communicating practical truth inevitably has a rhetoric dimension.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Indeed Plato did give an account of ‘real’ rhetoric, or rhetoric based on knowledge, but in this account rhetoric is just a part of philosophy. The real orator would be a philosopher-king.

  2. 2.

    Commentary of the translator in: Aristotle (1926).

  3. 3.

    ‘Rhetoric is useful, because the true and the just are naturally superior to their opposites’ (1255a18).

  4. 4.

    Elaborated in book III of EN.

  5. 5.

    Cooper (1994, 197): ‘and not merely by what he says’.

  6. 6.

    Engberg-Petersen (1996) hints at several places where this ‘austere conception’ of rhetoric can be found.

  7. 7.

    1355a17 ‘pros ta endoxa’; cfr. 1356b33 ‘endoxon’, cfr. 1357a14., 1359a30: ‘things which may possibly happen or not’-endechetai’.

  8. 8.

    1359b1: our examination is limited to finding out whether such things are possible or impossible for us to perform.

  9. 9.

    As Jaeger (1957) elaborates, the difference is clearly visible in the use Plato and Aristotle make of examples from medicine.

  10. 10.

    Jaeger (1957) states that Aristotle’s examples from medicine are meant to support this claim. According to Aristotle theoretical knowledge described in books is only good when it is supplemented by experience. Ultimately the doctor is educated by a doctor.

  11. 11.

    I’ve elaborated this interpretation of Aristotle’s methodology in Becker (2004).

  12. 12.

    Trevett even speaks about ‘a curious neglect of genuine political and forensic oratory’. Quoted in Graff (2001).

Bibliography

  • Aristotle. 1926. (Rhet.) The art of rhetoric. Trans. H. Freese. London: Loeb Classical Library

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1928. (Top.) Topics. Trans. G. Mure. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1934. (Pol.) Politics. Trans. H. Rackham. London: Loeb Classical Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1936. (EN) Nicomachean ethics. Trans. H. Rackham. London: Loeb Classical Library

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, M. 2004. Virtue ethics, applied ethics and rationality twenty-three years after after virtue. South African Journal of Philosophy 23(2): 25–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunschwig, J. 1996. Aristotle’s rhetoric as a ‘counterpart’ to dialectic. In Essays on Aristotle’s rhetoric, ed. A. Oxenberg-Rorty, 142–173. London: Berkeley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, J. 1994. Ethico-political theory in Aristotle’s rhetoric. In Aristotle’s rhetoric, philosophical essays, ed. D. Furley and A. Nehamans, 193–210. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engberg-Pedersen, T. 1996. Is there an ethical dimension to Aristotelian rhetoric? In Essays on Aristotle’s rhetoric, ed. A. Oxenberg-Rorty, 116–141. London: Berkeley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garver, E. 1994. Aristotle’s rhetoric, an art of character. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graff, R. 2001. Reading and the ‘written style’ in Aristotle’s rhetoric. Rhetoric Society Quarterly 31(4): 19–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halliwell, S. 1994. Popular morality, philosophical ethics and the rhetoric. In Aristotle’s rhetoric, philosophical essays, ed. D. Furley and A. Nehamans, 211–230. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irwin, T. 1996. Ethics in the rhetoric and in the ethics. In Essays on Aristotle’s rhetoric, ed. A. Oxenberg-Rorty, 142–173. London: Berkeley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaeger, W. 1957. Aristotle’s use of medicine and Aristotle’s use of medicine as a method in his ethics. Journal of Hellenic Studies 77(1): 54–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S. 1988. An analysis and defense of Aristotle’s method in NE I and X. Ancient Philosophy 8(1): 63–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCabe, M. 1994. Arguments in context: Aristotle’s defense of rhetoric. In Aristotle’s rhetoric, philosophical essays, ed. D. Furley and A. Nehamans, 129–165. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, C. 1993. The polis as rhetorical community. Rhetorica 11(3): 211–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 1925. Gorgias. Trans. W. Lamb. London: Loeb Classical Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schütrumpf, E. 1994. Some observations on the introduction to Aristotle’s rhetoric. In Aristotle’s rhetoric, philosophical essays, ed. D. Furley and A. Nehamans, 99–116. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprute, J. 1994. Aristotle and the legitimacy of rhetoric. In Aristotle’s rhetoric, philosophical essays, ed. D. Furley and A. Nehamans, 117–128. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Triadafilopoulos, T. 1999. Politics, speech, and the art of persuasion: Toward an Aristotelian conception of the public sphere. Journal of Politics 61(3): 741–757.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marcel Becker .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Becker, M. (2013). Aristotelian Ethics and Aristotelian Rhetoric. In: Huppes-Cluysenaer, L., Coelho, N. (eds) Aristotle and The Philosophy of Law: Theory, Practice and Justice. Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice, vol 23. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6031-8_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics