Advertisement

A Neo-Aristotelian Notion of Reciprocity: About Civic Friendship and (the Troublesome Character of) Right Judicial Decisions

  • Iris van Domselaar
Chapter
Part of the Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice book series (IUSGENT, volume 23)

Abstract

This chapter argues that a neo-Aristotelian approach can play a valuable role in accounting for reciprocity in adjudication. It can solve the central flaws that an “adjudication as applied moral theory” approach faces. In addition, the author asserts that a neo-Aristotelian approach to adjudication needs the concept of civic friendship in order to really account for reciprocity in adjudication. Citizens will have a reason to accept the painful burden of a particular judicial decision if the decision is made by a judge who is both judicially wise and a civic friend.

It will be shown that this neo-Aristotelian approach comes with a “troublesome” judicial phenomenology. Both the judge and the losing party will be confronted with the inescapable limits of reciprocity. Not only will the actual grounds of judicial decisions remain to some extent inarticulate, also, these decisions will sometimes come with a genuine moral loss.

Keywords

Moral Theory Practical Wisdom Judicial Decision Fellow Citizen Constitutional Democracy 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Notes

Acknowledgement

The author wishes to thank her colleagues Liesbeth Huppes-Cluysenaer, Frans Jacobs, Dorien Pessers and Joep van der Vliet for discussions and their generous help in preparing this chapter. In particular she owes thanks to an anonymous referee for his constructive and insightful comments.

Bibliography

  1. Alexy, Robert. 2004. The nature of legal philosophy. Ratio Juris 17(2): 156–167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Altman, Andrew. 1986. Legal realism, critical legal studies, and Dworkin. Philosophy and Public Affairs 15(3): 205–236.Google Scholar
  3. Annas, Julia. 1987. Comments on John M. Cooper’s “Political animals and civic friendship”. Paper read at XI. Symposium Aristotelicum, at Friedrichshafen/Bodensee.Google Scholar
  4. Aristotle. 2002. Nichomachean ethics: Translation, introduction, and commentary. ed. Sarah Broadie, and Christoffer Rowe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Barbour, John D. 1983. Tragedy and ethical reflection. The Journal of Religion 63(1): 1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Claassen, Rutger, and Marcus Düwell. 2012. The foundations of capability theory: Comparing Nussbaum and Gewirth. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 1–18. http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10677-012-9361-8Google Scholar
  7. Cooper, John M. 1999. Reason and emotion: Essays on ancient moral psychology and ethical theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Cooper, John M. 1999. Aristotle on the forms of friendship. In Reason and emotion. Essays on ancient moral psychology and ethical theory. Princeton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
  9. de Wijze, Stephen. 2004. Tragic remorse: The anguish of dirty hands. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 7: 453–471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Dworkin, Ronald. 1985. A matter of principle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Dworkin, Ronald. 1986. Law’s empire. Belknap: Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  12. Dworkin, Ronald. 2005. Taking rights seriously. London: Duckworth (1977).Google Scholar
  13. Dworkin, Ronald. 2011. Justice for hedgehogs. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Frank, Jerome. 1931. Law and the modern mind. New York: Brentano’s Publisher.Google Scholar
  15. Geuss, Raymond. 2008. Philosophy and real politics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Hackett, Rosalind I.J. 2001. Is religion good news or bad news for women? Martha Nussbaum’s creative solution to conflicting rights. Soundings 83(3–4): 615–25.Google Scholar
  17. Hart, H.L.A. 1961. Clarendon law series. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Hawthorn, Geoffrey (ed.). 2005. Bernard Williams. In In the beginning was the deed: Realism and moralism in political argument. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Holmes, Oliver Wendell. 1897. The path of the law. Harvard Law Review 10: 457.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Kramer, Matthew H. 2007. Objectivity and the rule of law, Cambridge introductions to philosophy and law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Leib, Ethan J. (2006). Friendship and the law. University of California Law Review 54: 631–707.Google Scholar
  22. Llewellyn, Karl. 1960. The common law tradition: Deciding appeals. Boston, MA/Toronto: Little, Brown and Company.Google Scholar
  23. Lyons, David. 1984a. Ethics and the rule of law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Lyons, David. 1984b. Justification and judicial responsibility. California Law Review 72(2): 178–199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. McDowell, John. 1998. Mind, value and reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Nussbaum, Martha. 1990. Love’s knowledge: Essays on philosophy and literature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Nussbaum, Martha. 1998. Victims and agents: What Greek tragedies can teach us about sympathy and responsibility. Boston Review.Google Scholar
  28. Nussbaum, Martha. 2000. The costs of tragedy: Some moral limits of cost–benefit analysis. Journal of Legal Studies XXIX: 1005–1036.Google Scholar
  29. Nussbaum, Martha. 2001. The fragility of goodness: Luck and ethics in Greek tragedy and philosophy, Rev ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
  30. Nussbaum, Martha. 2006. Frontiers of justice: Disability, nationality, species membership. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  31. Nussbaum, Martha. 2007. The Supreme Court, 2006 term. Foreword: Constitutions and capabilities: ‘perception’ against lofty formalism. Harvard Law Review 121(1): 4–97.Google Scholar
  32. Nussbaum, Martha. 2011. Creating capabilities: The human development approach. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Rawls, John. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press (1999).Google Scholar
  34. Rawls, John. 2005. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  35. Richardson, Henry S. 1997. Practical reasoning about final ends, Cambridge studies in philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Scharffs, Brett G. 2000. Adjudication and the problems of incommensurability. William and Mary Law Review 42: 1369–1435.Google Scholar
  37. Schauer, Frederick. 1985. Easy cases. California Law Review 58: 399–440.Google Scholar
  38. Simpson, Peter. 1992. Contemporary virtue ethics and Aristotle. Review of Metaphysics 45(3): 503–524.Google Scholar
  39. Solum, Lawrence B. 2003. Virtue jurisprudence: A virtue-centered theory of judging. Metaphilosophy 34(1/2): 178–213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Soper, Philip. 1977. Legal theory and the obligation of a judge: The Hart/Dworkin dispute. Michigan Law Review 75(3): 473–519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Timmons, Mark. 1987. Foundationalism and the structure of ethical justification. Ethics 97(3): 595–609.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Van Domselaar, I. 2010. Tragic choice as a legal concept. Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 119: 105–116.Google Scholar
  43. Waldron, Jeremy. 1987. Theoretical foundations of liberalism. The Philosophical Quarterly 37(147): 127–150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Wellman, Christopher Heath. 1995. On conflicts between rights. Law and philosophy 14(3/4): 271–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Wenar, Leif. 2011. Rights. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: Stanford University.Google Scholar
  46. Wiggins, David. 1980. Deliberation and practical reason. In Essays on Aristotle’s ethics, ed. Amélie O. Rorty. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  47. Williams, Bernard. 1985. Ethics and the limits of philosophy. London: Fontana Press.Google Scholar
  48. Williams, Bernard. 2001. Liberalism and loss. In The legacy of Isaiah Berlin, ed. Mark Lilla, Ronald Dworkin, and Kelly Aileen. New York: New York Review Book.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht. 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Amsterdam Law SchoolUniversity of AmsterdamAmsterdamThe Netherlands

Personalised recommendations