Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Studies in Brain and Mind ((SIBM,volume 6))

Abstract

In “Consciousness and the Introspection of ‘Qualitative Simples’” Paul Churchland criticizes a familiar family of anti-physicalist arguments, including Thomas Nagel’s (1974) “What is it like to be a bat?” argument, Frank Jackson’s (1982, 1986, 1995) knowledge argument, and related arguments developed by David Chalmers (1996, 2010) and others. In Churchland’s view, those arguments lead to the pessimistic view that science can shed no light on the qualitative features of conscious experience. He provides good reasons to reject that pessimistic view. However, I will argue, he is wrong to associate it with at least two of the anti-physicalist arguments he considers: the knowledge and conceivability arguments. Proponents of those arguments can share Churchland’s more optimistic view about the science of consciousness. Indeed, at least some proponents, including Chalmers, advocate a similar view. Churchland also attacks the anti-physicalist arguments more directly, identifying and criticizing assumptions that he sees as underlying them. But, I will argue, those attacks are at best inconclusive, at least with respect to the knowledge and conceivability arguments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The most widely discussed version of the conceivability argument (Chalmers 1996, 2010) involves the claim that zombies (creatures that lack consciousness but are physically identical to conscious human beings) are conceivable. See Sect. 5.4.

  2. 2.

    I restrict my claims to the knowledge and conceivability arguments mostly because the other anti-physicalist arguments Churchland discusses have been less well developed. But I suspect that parallel conclusions about those other arguments could be defended on similar grounds.

  3. 3.

    Page numbers taken from Chap. 4 of this volume. Citations refer to that chapter unless otherwise specified.

  4. 4.

    The qualification “as traditionally conceived” is vital. Physical science might be conceived broadly so as to include, for example, protophenomenal properties (Stoljar 2001). In that case, the knowledge and conceivability arguments would be compatible with the claim that physical science might exhaustively explain consciousness.

  5. 5.

    Pete Mandick (2009) develops an argument along roughly these lines. I criticize it in Alter (2008).

  6. 6.

    If the Hurvich-Jameson model (or the model plus other physical truths) appears initially to explain all qualitative features of seeing red, this may stem from a tendency to conceive of the model in phenomenal terms, for example, in terms of what it is like to see a certain after image. I have been assuming that the model is characterized in entirely physical terms. Otherwise, if the model is specified partly in phenomenal terms, then even if Mary could deduce the phenomenal character of seeing red from the model this would not support physicalism or threaten the knowledge argument.

  7. 7.

    See also Chalmers’ (1995, 1996) discussion of the principle of structural coherence. Churchland’s view also seems to align well with Thomas Nagel’s (1974, p. 449) suggestion that we develop “an objective phenomenology not dependent on empathy or the imagination” the goal of which “would be to describe, at least in part, the subjective character of experiences in a form comprehensible to beings incapable of having those experiences.”

  8. 8.

    Jackson (1998, 2003, 2007) has since rejected the knowledge argument, but not for the reasons Churchland recommends. For criticisms of Jackson’s reasons, see Alter (2007).

  9. 9.

    I assume that “scientific knowledge” refers to knowledge of the sort Mary learns pre-emergence by watching science lectures on black-and-white television; and that “subjective knowledge” refers to knowledge of what it is like, otherwise known as phenomenal knowledge.

  10. 10.

    That summary omits various details. For example, as Chalmers (2004b, 2010) argues, it is best to formulate the knowledge argument so that the conclusion comes out as a disjunction: either physicalism is false or Russellian monism is true. Also, references to the complete physical truth should strictly speaking be to a conjunction of the complete physical truth, a second-order ‘that’s all’ truth, and the complete indexical truth (loc cit.).

  11. 11.

    For discussions of these assumptions, see Alter and Howell (2012) and Chalmers (2010). Churchland does not cite any of the post-1996 philosophical literature on this subject, other than his own contributions.

  12. 12.

    Or if he does not, and he is suggesting instead that knowledge of what it is like is only partly non-propositional, then the propositional part is left over to fuel the knowledge argument.

  13. 13.

    For arguments defending the propositional knowledge claim, see Lycan (1996), Alter (2001), Stanley and Williamson (2001), Alter and Howell (2009), and Howell (2012).

  14. 14.

    However, Friends of Mary would quibble with the first sentence in the quoted paragraph if it is meant to refer to every conceivable cognitive creature.

  15. 15.

    For more on protophenomenal properties and Russellian monism, see Alter and Nagasawa (2012).

  16. 16.

    (C) involves some simplification. Here is a more precise formulation: there are truths about consciousness that are not metaphysically necessitated by the conjunction of the complete truth about causal/nomic spatio-temporal structure-and-dynamics, the complete indexical truth, and a second-order “that’s all” truth. See footnote 10.

  17. 17.

    However, for an interesting defense of the analogy, see Pereboom (2011). I criticize Pereboom’s argument in Alter (2012).

  18. 18.

    Daniel Stoljar (2006) develops the ignorance line in detail. For criticisms of Stoljar’s arguments, see Alter (2009), Bennett (2009), Chalmers (2010), and Gertler (2009).

  19. 19.

    See Balog (1999) for a development of this challenge.

  20. 20.

    For helpful comments, I thank David J. Chalmers, Robert J. Howell, Rekha Nath, and Derk Pereboom.

References

  • Alter, T. 2001. Know-how, ability, and the ability hypothesis. Theoria 67: 229–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alter, T. 2007. Does representationalism undermine the knowledge argument? In Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge: New essays on consciousness and physicalism, ed. T. Alter and S. Walter, 65–76. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alter, T. 2008. Phenomenal knowledge without experience. In The case for qualia, ed. E. Wright, 247–267. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alter, T. 2009. Does the ignorance hypothesis undermine the conceivability and knowledge arguments? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79: 756–765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alter, T. 2012. Review of Derk Pereboom’s Consciousness and the prospects of physicalism. Mind 121: 1115–1124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alter, T., and R.J. Howell. 2009. A dialogue on consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alter, T., and R.J. Howell (eds.). 2012. Consciousness and the mind-body problem: A reader. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alter, T., and Y. Nagasawa. 2012. What is Russellian monism? Journal of Consciousness Studies 19(9–10): 67–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alter, T., and S. Walter (eds.). 2007. Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balog, K. 1999. Conceivability, possibility, and the mind-body problem. Philosophical Review 108: 497–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, K. 2009. What you don’t know can hurt you. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79: 766–774.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (ed.). 2009. The oxford handbook of philosophy and neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D.J. 1995. Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 2: 200–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D.J. 1996. The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D.J. 2004a. How can we construct a science of consciousness? In The cognitive neurosciences III, ed. M. Gazzaniga. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Reprinted in Chalmers 2010: 37–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D.J. 2004b. Phenomenal concepts and the knowledge argument. In There’s something about Mary: Essays on phenomenal consciousness and Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument, ed. P. Ludlow, D. Stoljar, and Y. Nagasawa, 269–298. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D.J. 2010. The character of consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M. (ed.). 2004. The cognitive neurosciences III. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gertler, B. 2009. The role of ignorance in the problem of consciousness. Critical notice of Stoljar 2009. Noûs 43: 378–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G., and D. Davidson (eds.). 1972. The semantics of natural language. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howell, R.J. 2012. Consciousness and the limits of objectivity: The case for subjective physicalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 1982. Epiphenomenal qualia. The Philosophical Quarterly 32(127): 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 1986. What Mary didn’t know. The Journal of Philosophy 83: 291–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 1995. Postscript. In Contemporary materialism: A reader, ed. P. Moser and J.D. Trout, 184–189. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 1998a. Postscript on qualia. In Mind, method, and conditionals: Selected essays, ed. F. Jackson, 76–79. London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 1998b. Mind, method, and conditionals: Selected essays. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 2003. Mind and illusion. In Minds and persons: Royal institute of philosophy supplement, 53, ed. O’Hear, 251–271. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 2007. The knowledge argument, diaphanousness, representationalism. In Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge, ed. T. Alter and S. Walter, 65–76. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. 1972. Naming and necessity. In The semantics of natural language, ed. G. Harman and D. Davidson, 253–355. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1983a. Postscript to ‘mad pain and martian pain’. In Philosophical papers, vol. 1, 130–132. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1983b. Philosophical papers, vol. 1. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1988. What experience teaches. In Proceedings of the Russellian society, 499–518. Sydney: University of Sydney. Reprinted in Lycan 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludlow, P., D. Stoljar, and Y. Nagasawa (eds.). 2004. There’s something about Mary: Essays on phenomenal consciousness and Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W.G. (ed.). 1990. Mind and cognition: A Reader. Cambridge: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W.G. 1996. Consciousness and experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandick, P. 2009. The neurophilosophy of subjectivity. In The oxford handbook of philosophy and neuroscience, ed. J. Bickle, 601–618. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moser, P., and J.D. Trout. 1995. Contemporary materialism: A reader. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. 1974. What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review 4: 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nemirow, L. 1980. Review of Thomas Nagel’s mortal questions. Philosophical Review 89(3): 473–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nemirow, L. 1990. Physicalism and the cognitive role of acquaintance. In Mind and cognition: A reader, ed. W.G. Lycan, 490–499. Cambridge: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nemirow, L. 2007. So this is what it’s like: A defense of the ability hypothesis. In Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge, ed. T. Alter and S. Walter, 32–51. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • O’Hear, A. 2003. Minds and persons: Royal institute of philosophy supplement, 53. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. 2011. Consciousness and the prospects of physicalism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., and T. Williamson. 2001. Knowing how. The Journal of Philosophy 98: 411–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. 2001. Two conceptions of the physical. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62: 253–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. 2006. Ignorance and imagination: The epistemic origin of the problem of consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, E. 2008. The case for qualia. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Torin Alter .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Alter, T. (2014). Churchland on Arguments Against Physicalism. In: Brown, R. (eds) Consciousness Inside and Out: Phenomenology, Neuroscience, and the Nature of Experience. Studies in Brain and Mind, vol 6. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6001-1_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics