Skip to main content

Consequentialist and Nonconsequentialist Dimensions in the Ethical Evaluation of Inequality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Spheres of Global Justice

Abstract

The need to go beyond the standard welfarist framework of consequentialist evaluative judgements is widely felt in social ethics and normative economics. However, there is much disagreement about the choice of a way out. The relationships between a welfarist perspective on well-being and consequentialism are under investigation. In view of the conceptual difficulties which surround the notion of an intrinsic value of freedom of choice, as well as the need to take into account both the choice dimension and pieces of information about the consequences of action (or organization), an enlarged consequentialist viewpoint on matters of inequality is advocated. It is argued that this should lead to a perspective on poverty problems that is able to combine welfare and choice information.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    I thank Peter Koller, Michael Schefczyk and Véronique Munoz-Dardé for their very helpful remarks and discussion on the first version of the article in the context of European project “Applied Global Justice”, and Antoinette Baujard for drawing my attention to a relevant reference. The final version has benefited from ongoing work in research projects CEEI (Bourgogne/Franche Comté inter-regional initiative for higher education [PRES]) and CONREP (Franche-Comté regional council & Université de Franche-Comté).

  2. 2.

    “Consequentialism” will be defined here as a property of judgments, evaluation procedures or arguments, namely, that of being based exclusively on properties of the outcomes (the so-called “consequences”) of social interactions. It will not be presupposed (as is sometimes the case in moral philosophy) that the dependence on consequences reflects impartiality.

  3. 3.

    A Pareto improvement is a shift from one social state of affairs to another one, which benefits some and leaves nobody worse off (“weak Pareto criterion”) or, in a less widely used version, benefits all (“strong Pareto criterion”). When a Pareto improvement is no longer available, Pareto efficiency is reached.

  4. 4.

    Standard critiques of these doctrines include, respectively, the following: utilitarianism offers an excuse for the illegitimate sacrifice of the welfare of some individuals; full welfare egalitarianism presupposes unreasonable political control for assessment and implementation, and it cancels the potential benefits associated with ethically unproblematic inequalities. In addition, both views rely on unwarranted interpersonal welfare comparisons.

  5. 5.

    See Guibet Lafaye 2009.

  6. 6.

    Correspondingly, one attractive interpretation of the Pareto principle is the following: if a judgment is such that nobody in the considered society is in a position to express it sincerely, there is nothing about that judgment to be taken into account for ethical judgment. See Kolm 1996. I have examined the force of the reasons behind the Pareto principle in my 1999a, b, 2005.

  7. 7.

    To keep the argument simple, I set aside the problems associated with Pareto improvements that appear to be inferior to other Pareto improvements, which would not remain easily reachable if the former were to be approved and implemented. Surely there are plenty of reasons, from an egalitarian perspective, to operate distinctions between good and less good Pareto improvement. However, here I concentrate on a more limited (and easier) question: does the egalitarian have good reason to reject a Pareto improvements on grounds of equality even when the considered improvement involves no blocking of superior improvements in the future?

  8. 8.

    One plausible such correlated structural change, which may affect the fairness of opportunities in life, is social segregation in the school system, with increasingly well-funded and prestigious private schools developing in response to the demand for above-the-average education among the new privileged sections of society.

  9. 9.

    These estimations were actually the basis for the Arrow—Robinson debate on poverty. See Robinson 1997.

  10. 10.

    Equality-motivated social movements among the rich are no exception and are often successful. Consider the following example. The figures given by the Health Ministry in France indicate that in 2004, the net average annual income of sector-one surgeons is 70,000 euros, while that of sector-two surgeons is 120,000 euros. In the newspapers (e.g., Ouest France August 6, 2004), we learn that there is a social movement among surgeons. In response to this social unrest, the Health minister elaborates a complex scheme to “save French surgery,” which is designed to raise the standard of living of both categories, while helping to bridge the gap between the two income categories. The scheme is based on higher payment for acts and some new insurance subventions. Unexpectedly enough, the scheme becomes a source of additional social unrest: some surgeons claim it sums up to mere “compensation subventions” and go on strike to gain more.

  11. 11.

    Attention should be paid here to relevant aspects of social life, such as the quality of public services, the level of development of associative and cultural life, and the quality of social relationships across groups in the population.

  12. 12.

    See, for example, Kenneth J. Arrow 1982. He writes: “What has become clear is that hunger and ultimately famine are basically questions of the distribution of income and the entitlements to food. […] At higher levels of consumption, hunger fades away as a basic problem but is replaced by other needs, including medicine, shelter, and the like.”

  13. 13.

    According to this interpretation, the relative importance of the consumption of the last unit of a good is less than that of the consumption of the first units because real needs are most likely to have been already satisfied to some extent. It seems quite obvious to me that the plausibility of such an interpretation depends on the nature of the good and also on the structure of subjective preferences. Although it may be quite plausible in some contexts, the general plausibility of the interpretation is quite dubious. On economic approaches to egalitarianism, see Fleurbaey 1996.

  14. 14.

    More choice, however, is not always better. See Lu et al. 2005.

  15. 15.

    QALYs—quality adjusted life years—are sometimes proposed as an operational tool for implementing utilitarian—or, more broadly conceived, consequentialist—prioritization in health care.

  16. 16.

    One of the best available methodological syntheses is found in Leplège and Coste 2001.

  17. 17.

    Roughly speaking, this means that, if the best element in set A (for an individual) is preferred or equivalent to that in set B, then choosing in A is preferred or equivalent to choosing in B; and if B is strictly included in A, choosing in A is preferred to choosing in B.

  18. 18.

    Sen (1987: 75–76) insists that “seeing consequences in very broad terms, including the value of actions performed or the disvalue of violated rights” is helpful and essential, although he also argues that this cannot be seen as bridging the gap between consequentialist evaluation and what he describes as consequence-sensitive deontology.

  19. 19.

    Research on which inequalities matter is further exemplified by Anne Phillips 1999, among others.

Bibliography

  • Anand, P., and A. Wailoo. 1996. Utilities vs. rights to publicly provided goods: Arguments and evidence from health-care rationing. Open Discussion Papers in Economics (The Open University), No. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K.J. 1982. Why people go hungry. (Review of Amartya Sen’s book, Poverty and Famines: an Essay on Entitlement and Deprivation). Available at: http://www.finance.commerce.ubc.ca.

  • Fleurbaey, M. 1996. Théories économiques de la justice. Paris: Economica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gravel, N. 1994. Can a ranking of opportunity sets attach an intrinsic importance to freedom of choice? American Economic Review: Papers and Proceedings 84: 454–458.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gravel, N. 1998. Ranking opportunity sets on the basis of their freedom of choice and their ability to satisfy preferences: A difficulty. Social Choice and Welfare 15: 371–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guibet Lafaye, C. 2009. Modèles de la cohesion sociale. Archives Européennes de Sociologie L 3: 389–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolm, S.C. 1996. Moral public choice. Public Choice 87: 117–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leplège, A., and J. Coste. 2001. Mesure de la Santé Perceptuelle et de la Qualité de Vie: méthodes et applications. Paris: Editions Estem.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lu, H.C., M. Chen, and J.J. Chang. 2005. Are more alternatives better for decision-makers? A note on the role of decision cost. Theory and Decision 58(3): 283–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oliver, P., G. Marwell, and R. Texera. 1985. A theory of the critical mass, I. Interdependence, group heterogeneity, and the production of collective action. The American Journal of Sociology 91(3): 522–556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, A. 1999. Which equalities matter? Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Picavet, E. 1999a. De l’efficacité à la normativité. Revue économique 50(4): 833–858.

    Google Scholar 

  • Picavet, E. 1999b. La rationalité de l’adoption du ‘principe de Pareto’. In Pareto aujourd’hui, ed. A. Bouvier, 243–271. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Picavet, E. 2005. The significance of Pareto’s attack on Hobbes and natural law theorists. In Rechtsphilosophische Hefte, XI: Leviathan between the wars, ed. L. Foisneau, J.-C. Merle, and T. Sorell, 49–62. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, P. 1997. Interview by Peter Robinson. Rich man, poor man. Hoover Digest no.4. Hoover Institution. Available at: http://www-hoover.stanford.edu/publications/digest/974/interview.html.

  • Sen, A.K. 1987. On ethics and economics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emmanuel Picavet .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Picavet, E. (2013). Consequentialist and Nonconsequentialist Dimensions in the Ethical Evaluation of Inequality. In: Merle, JC. (eds) Spheres of Global Justice. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5998-5_39

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics