Advertisement

Natural Right and Coercion

  • Ana Marta GonzálezEmail author
Chapter
  • 1k Downloads
Part of the Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice book series (IUSGENT, volume 22)

Abstract

What is the relationship between natural right and coercion? After an introduction aimed at clarifying the implications of the Aristotelian notion of natural right for this topic, I try to answer this question by focusing in Kant’s approach to natural right. While Kant is not usually considered a natural right thinker, I argue that his reflection on natural right retains crucial elements of the iusnaturalist tradition, and serves to the purpose of highlighting the relationship between natural right and coercion. Kant points out that natural right is not to be divided into natural and social right, but rather into natural and civil right. In this division natural right is to be identified with private right (MM, 6: 242). A significant feature of private right is that the distinction between “mine” and “thine” is not guaranteed by public laws. In the state of nature, therefore, this distinction is only a provisional one, although it can be called juridical by comparison (MM, 6: 256–7). However, since all law—hence also natural law- is inseparably linked to coercion (MM, 6: 231) how are we to justify coercion in the state of nature?

Keywords

Distributive Justice Common Good External Object Political Life Civil Condition 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Aquinas, T. 1964. In decem libros ethicorum Aristotelis ad Nicomachum Expositio. ed. 3ª. Marietti: Torino.Google Scholar
  2. Arendt, H. 1951. The origins of totalitarianism. New York: Meridian Books.Google Scholar
  3. Arendt, H. 1958. The human condition. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  4. Aristotle. 1968. The politics of Aristotle. Translated with an introduction notes and appendixes by Ernest Barker. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  5. Aristotle. 2002. Nicomachean ethics. Trans., introd. and commentary by Sarah Broadie and Christopher Rowe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Dodson, K. 1995. Kant’s idea of the Social Contract. In Proceedings of the eight international Kant congress. Memphis 1995, vol. II, part 2, ed. H. Robinson. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
  7. González, A.M. 2006. Moral, razón y naturaleza. Una investigación sobre Tomás de Aquino, 2nd ed. Pamplona: Eunsa.Google Scholar
  8. González, A.M. 2008. Justicia como virtud artificial en David Hume. Elementos para una teoría psico-social de la acción. Pensamiento 64(239): 97–127.Google Scholar
  9. González, A.M. 2009. Alcance y límites del deber de obediencia al gobierno según Hume. Tópicos. Revista de Filosofía, nº 37.Google Scholar
  10. González, A.M. 2010. Kant and a culture of freedom. Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 93: 3.Google Scholar
  11. González, A.M. 2011. Culture as mediation. Kant on nature, culture and morality. Hildesheim/New York: Georg Olms.Google Scholar
  12. Henrich, D. 1976. Kant über die Revolution. In Materialen zu Kants Rechtsphilosophie, Batscha, Z. (hrsg),Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, pp. 359–365.Google Scholar
  13. Hobbes, T. 1966. Leviathan. In The english works of Thomas Hobbes. Collected and edited by Sir William Molesworth, vol. III, 1889, 2nd reprint. Aalen: Scientia Verlag.Google Scholar
  14. Hume, D. 1978. In A treatise of human nature, 2nd ed, ed. L.A. Selby-Bigge and P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  15. Hüning, D. 1995. Kant auf den Spuren von Thomas Hobbes. In Proceedings of the international Kant congress. Memphis 1995, vol.II, part 2, ed. H. Robinson, 760–771. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Kaulbach, F. 1976. Naturrecht und Erfahrungsbegriff im Zeichen der Anwendung der kantischen Rechtsphilosophie; dargestellt an den Thesen von P.J.A. Feuerbach. In Materialen zu Kants Rechtsphilosophie, Batscha, Z. (hrsg), 193–203. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  17. Kuehn, M. 1987. Scottish common sense in Germany, 1768–1800. A contribution to the history of critical philosophy. Montreal-Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Kuehn, M. 2001. Kant. A biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Murphy, M. 1995. Was Hobbes a legal positivist? Ethics 105(4): 846–873.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Nehring, R. 2009. Kritik des Common Sense. Gesunder Menschenverstand, reflektierende Urteilskraft und Gemeinsinn- der Sensus communis bei Kant. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.Google Scholar
  21. Patrone, T. 2008. How Kant’s conception of reason implies a liberal politics. An interpretation of the ‘Doctrine of Right’ (Rechtslehre). Lewiston: The Edwin Mellen Press.Google Scholar
  22. Riedel, M. 1976. Hersschaft und Gesellschaft. Zum Legitimationsproblem des Politischen in der Philosophie. In Materialen zu Kants Rechtsphilosophie, Z. Batscha(hrsg). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  23. Ritter, Ch. 1971. Der Rechtsgedanke Kants nach den frühen Quellen. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
  24. Sharon Byrd, B., and J. Hruschka. 2010. Commentary to Kant’s doctrine of right. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Spaemann, R. 1976. Kants Kritik des Widerstandrechts. In Materialien zu Kants Rechtsphilosophie, ed. Z. Batscha, 347–358. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  26. Terada, T. 1995. The universal principle of right’ as the supreme principle of Kant’s practical philosophy. In Proceedings of the international Kant congress. Memphis 1995, vol.II, part 2, ed. H. Robinson. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Thucydides. 1965. History of the Peloponnesian War, book V, lxxxviii. Thucydides, with an English translation by Charles Forster Smith, in four volumes. London: William Heinemann Ltd.Google Scholar
  28. Tonella, G. 2009. L’Idea repubblicana in Kant. Tra riforma e negazione del diritto di resistenza. Padova: Il Poligrafo.Google Scholar
  29. Tuck, R. 1979. Natural rights theories. Their origin and development. London-New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  30. Vigo, A. 2008. Kant’s conception of natural right. In Contemporary perspectives on natural law. Natural law as a limiting concept, ed. A.M. González, 121–140. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  31. Ziegler, K. 1964. Der Kleine Pauly. Lexikon der Antike, I. Stuttgart: Alfred Druckenmüller Verlag.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht. 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.FilosofiaUniversidad de NavarraPamplonaSpain

Personalised recommendations