Skip to main content

Rationality and Experimental Economics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Epistemology of Decision

Part of the book series: SpringerBriefs in Philosophy ((BRIEFSPHILOSOPH))

  • 1016 Accesses

Abstract

The theory of rational choice (TRC) is a model of explanation used by social science theorists to interpret behavior. Initially, the theory was the dominant paradigm of economics. A fundamental postulate of neoclassical economics was that economic phenomena primarily resulted from the action of agents who were fully rational, equal and therefore indistinguishable from each other and all agents pursuing their own personal and individual gain.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Akerlof, G. (1970). The market for “Lemons”: Quality uncertainty and the market mechanism. Quarter Journal of Economics, 84(3), 488–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bagassi, M., & Macchi, L. (2006). Pragmatic approach to decision making under uncertainty: The case of the disjunction effect. Thinking and Reasoning, 12(3), 329–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, J. (1789). An Introduction to the Principle of Morals and Legislations. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertuglia, C. S., & Vaio, F. (2011). Complessità e modelli. Torino: Bollati Boringhieri.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K. (1994). Rationality in the centipede. In M. Kaufmann (Ed.), Proceedings of the 5th Conference on Theoretical Aspects of Reasoning about Knowledge (pp. 150–159). San Francisco: Morgan Kaufmann Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C. F., & Loewenstein, G. (2002). Behavioral economics: Past, present, future. Pasadena: Mimeo, Division of Humanities and Social Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C. F., & Thaler, R. (1995). Anomalies: Dictators, ultimatums, and manners. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 9(2), 209–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, M. K., Lakshminaryanan, V., & Santos, L. R. (2006). The evolution of our preferences: Evidence from capuchin monkey trading behavior. Journal of Political Economy, 114(3), 517–537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1996). Are humans good intuitive statisticians after all? Rethinking some conclusions from the literature on judgment under uncertainty. Cognition, 58, 1–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2001). Subjective, intersubjective, objective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., & Brannon, E. (2011). Space, time and number in the brain searching for the foundations of mathematical thought. San Diego: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eddy, D. M. (1982). Probabilistic reasoning in clinical medicine: Problems and opportunities. In D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, & A. Tversky (Eds.), Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases (pp. 249–267). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feynman, R. P. (1967). The character of physical law. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiedler, K. (1988). The dependence of the conjunction fallacy on subtle linguistic factors. Psychological Research, 50(2), 123–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M., & Savage, L. (1948). The utility analysis of choices involving risk. The Journal of Political Economy, 56(4), 279–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. R., & Gelman, R. (1978). The child’s understanding of number. Cambridge: Harvard university Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (2007). Gut feelings: The intelligence of the unconscious. New York: Viking Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., & Murray, D. J. (1987). Cognition as intuitive statistics. New York: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giorello, G., & Morini, S. (2008). Harsanyi visto da Giulio Giorello e Simona Morini. Roma: Luiss University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole, J. L. Morgan (Eds), Syntax and semantics. Speech acts (pp. 41–58). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, D. W., & Kahneman, D. (2002). Judgment heuristics: Human strengths or human weaknesses? In L. Aspinwall & U. Staudinger (Eds.), A psychology of human strengths: Perspectives on an emerging field (pp. 165–178). Washington: APA Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guala, F. (2005). The methodology of experimental economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ingrao, B., & Istrael, G. (1987). La mano invisibile. L’equilibrio economico nella storia della scienza. Roma-Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (1982). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1973). On the psychology of prediction. Psychological Review, 80(4), 237–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1974). Judgement under uncertainty. Heuristics and biases. Science, 185, 1124–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47(2), 263–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (2000). Presumptive meanings. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luce, R. D., & Raiffa, H. (1957). Games and decisions: Introduction and critical survey. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macdonald, R. R., & Gilhooly, K. J. (1990). More about Linda or conjunctions in context. European Journal of Cognitive Psychology, 2(1), 57–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marschak, J. (1951). Why « should » statisticians and businessmen maximize « moral expectation » ? In J. Neyman (Ed.), Paper presented at the Second Berkeley Symposium on Mathematical Statistics and Probability (Cowles Foundation Paper 53). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martignon, L., Vitouch, O., Takezawa, M., & Forster, M. R. (2003). Naive and yet enlightened: From natural frequencies to fast and frugal decision trees. In D. Hardman & L. Macchi (Eds.), Thinking: Psychological perspectives on reasoning, judgment and decision making (pp. 189–211). Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayo, D. G. (1996). Error and the growth of experimental knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moro, R. (2009). On the nature of the conjunction fallacy. Synthese, 171(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mosconi, G. (1990). Discorso e Pensiero. Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mosconi, G., & Macchi, L. (2001). Pragmatic rules and the conjunction fallacy. Mind & Society, 2(1), 31–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nash, J. F. (1949). Two person cooperative games. Econometrica, 21, 128–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piattelli Palmarini, M. (2005). Psicologia ed economia della scelta. Torino: Codice Edizioni.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saks, M. J., & Kidd, R. F. (1980). Human information processing and adjudication: Trial by heuristics. Law and Society Review, 15, 123–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P. A. (1938). A note on the pure theory of consumer’s behaviour. Economica, 5(17), 61–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sanfey, A. G., Rilling, J. K., Aronson, J. A., Nystrom, L. E., & Cohen, J. D. (2003). The neural basis of economic decision-making in the Ultimatum Game. Science, 300, 1755–1758.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shefrin, H., & Statman, M. (1985). The disposition to sell winners too early and ride losers too long. Journal of Finance, 40(3), 777–790.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sher, S., & McKenzie, C. R. M. (2006). Information leakage from logically equivalent frames. Cognition, 101, 467–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1972). Theories of bounded rationality. In C. B. McGuire & C. Radner (Eds.), Decision and organization (pp. 161–176). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., Cara, F., & Girotto, V. (1995). Relevance theory explains the selection task. Cognition, 57, 31–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance communication and cognition. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. (1983). Illusion and mirages in public policy. The Public Interest, 73, 60–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1983). Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: The conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. Psychological Review, 90(4), 293–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mario Graziano .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Graziano, M. (2013). Rationality and Experimental Economics. In: Epistemology of Decision. SpringerBriefs in Philosophy. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5428-7_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics