Functions and Mechanisms: A Perspectivalist View

Chapter
Part of the Synthese Library book series (SYLI, volume 363)

Abstract

Though the mechanical philosophy is traditionally associated with the rejection of teleological description and explanation, the theories of the contemporary physiological sciences, such as neuroscience, are replete with both functional and mechanistic descriptions. I explore the relationship between these two stances, showing how functional description contributes to the search for mechanisms. I discuss three ways that functional descriptions contribute to the explanations and mechanistic theories in contemporary neuroscience: as a way of tersely indicating an etiological explanation, as a way of framing constitutive explanations, and as a way of explaining the item by situating it within higher-level mechanisms. This account of functional description is ineliminably perspectival in the sense that it relies ultimately on decisions by an observer about what matters or is of interest in the system they study.

Keywords

NMDA Receptor Mechanistic Explanation Causal Structure Functional Description Mechanistic Description 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Allen, G. 2005. Mechanism, vitalism and organicism in late nineteenth and twentieth-century biology: The importance of historical context. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36: 261–283.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bartel, D.P. 2004. MicroRNAs: Genomics, biogenesis, mechanism, and function. Cell 116: 281–297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bechtel, W. 1989. Teleological functional analyses and the hierarchical organization of nature. In Teleology and natural science, ed. N. Rescher, 26–48. Lanham: University Press of America.Google Scholar
  4. Bechtel, W., and A. Abrahamsen. 2005. Explanation: A mechanistic alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36: 421–441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bechtel, W., and R. Richardson. 1993. Discovering complexity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Bigelow, R., and R. Pargetter. 1987. Functions. Journal of Philosophy 84: 181–197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Boorse, C. 1976. Wright on functions. In E. Sober 1984, 369–385.Google Scholar
  8. Brandon, R. 1990. Adaptation and environment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Burian, R.M. 1996. Underappreciated pathways toward molecular genetics as illustrated by Jean Brachet’s cytochemical embryology. In The philosophy and history of molecular biology: New perspectives, ed. S. Sarkar, 67–85. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Canfield, J. 1964. Teleological explanation in biology. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 14: 285–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Churchland, P.S., and T.J. Sejnowski. 1992. The computational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  12. Craver, C.F. 2001. Role functions, mechanism, and hierarchy. Philosophy of Science 68: 53–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Craver, C.F. 2002. Structures of scientific theories. In The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of science, ed. P.K. Machamer and M. Silberstein. Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  14. Craver, C.F. 2007. Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Craver, C.F., and L. Darden. 2001. Discovering mechanisms in neurobiology: The case of spatial memory. In Theory and method in the neurosciences, ed. P.K. Machamer, R. Grush, and P. McLaughlin, 112–137. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
  16. Cummins, R. 1975. Functional Analysis. Journal of Philosophy 72: 741–764. Repr. In E. Sober 1984, 386–407.Google Scholar
  17. Cummins, R. 1983. The nature of psychological explanation. Cambridge, MA: Bradford/MIT Press.Google Scholar
  18. Cummins, R.E. 2000. ‘How does it work’ versus ‘what are the laws?’ Two conceptions of psychological explanation. In Explanation and cognition, ed. F. Keil and Robert A. Wilson, 117–145. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  19. Darden, L. 2006. Reasoning in biological discoveries. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Dennett, D. 1987. The intentional stance. Cambridge: MIT Press/A Bradford Book.Google Scholar
  21. Des Chene, D. 2001. Spirits and clocks. Organism and machine in descartes. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Des Chene, D. 2005. Mechanisms of life in the seventeenth century. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36: 245–260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Dowe, P. 2000. Physical causation. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Garson, J. 2008. Function and teleology. In Companion to philosophy of biology, ed. A. Plutynski and S. Sarkar. Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  25. Gettins, P.G. 2002. Serpin structure, mechanism, and function. Chemical Reviews 102: 4751–4804.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Glennan, Stuart S. 1996. Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis 44: 49–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Glennan, Stuart S. 2002. Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science 69(Supplement): S342–S353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Glennan, Stuart S. 2009. Productivity, relevance and natural selection. Biology and Philosophy 24(3): 325–339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Good, B.L., and M.J. Eck. 2007. Mechanism and function of formins in the control of actin assembly. Annual Review of Biochemistry 76: 593–627.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Gould, S.J., and R.C. Lewontin. 1978. The spandrels of San Marco and the panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London 205: 581–598.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Gould, S.J., and E. Vrba. 1982. Exaptation – A missing term in the science of form. Paleobiology 8: 4–15.Google Scholar
  32. Haugeland, J. 1998. Having thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Hempel, C.G. 1965. Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
  34. Hull, D. 1974. Philosophy of biological science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  35. Kauer, J.A., and R.C. Malenka. 2007. Synaptic plasticity and addiction. Nature Reviews. Neuroscience 8: 844–858.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Kauffman, S.A. 1971. Articulation of parts explanation in biology and the rational search for them. In PSA 1970, ed. R.C. Buck and R.S. Cohen. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  37. Leunissen, M. 2007. The structure of teleological explanations in Aristotle: Theory and practice. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 33: 145–178.Google Scholar
  38. Lycan, W. 1987. Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.Google Scholar
  39. Machamer, P.K. 1977. Teleology and selective processes. In Logic, laws, and life: Some philosophical complications, Pittsburgh series in philosophy of science, ed. R. Colodny, 129–142. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
  40. Machamer, P.K., L. Darden, and C.F. Craver. 2000. Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science 67: 1–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Mackie, J.L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. Pelican Books, Middelessex.Google Scholar
  42. Mayer, et al. 1991. NMDA receptors: Physiological studies with divalent cations and competitive antagonists. In Neuroscience of the NMDA receptor, ed. A. Kosikowski and G. Barinuevo, 15–35. New York: VCH Publishers.Google Scholar
  43. Millikan, R. 1984. Language, thought, and other biological categories: New foundations for realism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  44. Neander, K. 1991. Functions as selected effects: The conceptual analysts defense. Philosophy of Science 58: 168–184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Osler, M. 2001. Whose ends? Teleology in early modern natural philosophy. Osiris 16: 151–168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Rowan, M.J., I. Klyubin, W.K. Cullen, and R. Anwyl. 2003. Synaptic plasticity in animal models of early Alzheimer’s disease. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences 358(1432): 821–828.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Ruse, M. 1971. Functional statements in biology. Philosophy of Science 38: 87–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Russell, G. 2010. In defense of Hume’s law. In Hume, ‘Is’ and ‘Ought’: New essays, ed. C. Pidgen. New York: Palgrave-MacMillan.Google Scholar
  49. Salmon, W.C. 1984. Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  50. Salmon, W.C. 1989. Four decades of scientific explanation. In Scientific explanation, Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science XVIII, ed. P. Kitcher and W. Salmon, 3–219. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  51. Salmon, W.C. 1994. Causality without counterfactuals. Philosophy of Science 61: 297–312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Schaffner, K.F. 1993. Discovery and explanation in biology and medicine. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  53. Sellars, W. 2007. The space of reasons: Selected essays of Wilfrid Sellars, ed. R. Brandom and K. Scharp. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  54. Shapin, S. 1996. The scientific revolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Shepherd, G. 1994. Neurobiology, 3rd ed. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  56. Sober, E. 1984. Conceptual issues in evolutionary biology. Cambridge, MA: Bradford/MIT Press.Google Scholar
  57. Thagard, P. 2000. Explaining disease: Correlations, causes and mechanisms. In Explanation and cognition, ed. R. Keil and R. Wilson. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  58. Toulmin, S. 1975. Concepts of function and mechanism in medicine and medical science. In Evaluation and explanation in the biomedical sciences, ed. H. Tristram Engelhardt Jr. and S.F. Spiker, 51–66. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Westfall, R.S. 1971. The construction of modern science. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
  60. Westfall, R.S. 1973. Science and religion in seventeenth-century England. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
  61. Wimsatt, W.C. 1972. Teleology and the logical structure of function statements. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 3: 1–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Wimsatt, W. 1974. Complexity and organization. In PSA 1972, Boston studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 2, ed. K.F. Schaffner and R.S. Cohen, 67–86. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Wimsatt, W.C. 1976. Reductive explanation: A functional account. In Sober 1984, Conceptual issues in evolutionary biology, 477–508. Cambridge, MA: Bradford/MIT Press..Google Scholar
  64. Woodward, J. 2003. Making things happen. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  65. Wright, L. 1973. Functions. Philosophical Review 85: 70–86. Repr. In Sober 1984, 347–368.Google Scholar
  66. Zhao, C., W. Deng, and F.H. Gage. 2008. Mechanisms and functional implications of adult neurogenesis. Cell 132: 645–660.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy-Neuroscience-Psychology ProgramWashington UniversitySt. LouisUSA

Personalised recommendations