Advertisement

‘Recalled to Study’—Descartes, Physico-Mathematicus

  • John Schuster
Chapter
Part of the Studies in History and Philosophy of Science book series (AUST, volume 27)

Abstract

This Chapter deals with the early physico-mathematics of Descartes in 1618–1620, which he pursued at first in conjunction with his mentor, Isaac Beeckman, who also had conveyed to him his first inkling of corpuscular-mechanism as an approach to natural philosophy. In the physico-mathematical program, the traditional view of the mixed mathematical sciences as subordinate to natural philosophy, and devoid of explanatory power, was challenged. The mixed mathematical disciplines were intended to become more integrally linked to questions of matter and cause; in other words, to questions of a natural philosophical type. In the case of Descartes and Beeckman, this meant an unsystematized, but firmly held, corpuscular-mechanism. The Chapter deals with three case studies of Descartes’ physico-mathematics: his manuscript on hydrostatics and the hydrostatic paradox; his work with Beeckman on the nature of accelerated fall, which is treated here in a new way as an exercise in physico-mathematics; and a widely overlooked, but extremely important, geometrical and physical optical fragment on refraction of light, adapted from bits of the work of Kepler.

Keywords

Tractive Force Dense Medium Parallel Component Causal Action Natural Fall 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

Works of Descartes and Their Abbreviations

  1. AT  =  Oeuvres de Descartes (revised edition, 12 vols.), edited by C. Adam and P. Tannery (Paris, 1964–76). References are by volume number (in roman) and page number (in Arabic).Google Scholar
  2. SG  =  The World and Other Writings, edited and translated by Stephen Gaukroger (Cambridge, 1998).Google Scholar
  3. MM  =  René Descartes, The Principles of Philosophy, translated by V. R. Miller and R. P. Miller, (Dordrecht, 1991)Google Scholar
  4. MSM  =  Rene Descartes, Le Monde, ou Traité de la lumière, translated by Michael S. Mahoney (New York, 1979).Google Scholar
  5. CSM(K)  =  The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, 3 vols., translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch, and (for vol. 3) Anthony Kenny, (Cambridge, 1988) References are by volume number (in roman) and page number (in arabic).Google Scholar
  6. HR  =  The Philosophical Works of Descartes, vol I translated by E.S. Haldane and G.R.T. Ross (Cambridge, 1968 [1st ed. 1911]).Google Scholar

Other

  1. Beeckman, Isaac. 1644. Mathematicao-physicarum meditationum, quaestionum, solutionum centuria. Utrecht: Petrus Daniel Sloot.Google Scholar
  2. Beeckman, I. 1939–53. Journal tenu par Isaac Beeckman de 1604 à 1634, 4 vols, ed. C. de Waard. The Hague: Nijhoff.Google Scholar
  3. Bennett, Jim. 1998. Practical geometry and operative knowledge. Configurations 6(2): 195–222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. van Berkel, Klass. 1983. Isaac Beeckman (1588–1637) En De Mechanisering van Het Wereldbeeld. Amsterdam: Rodophi.Google Scholar
  5. van Berkel, Klaas. 2000. Descartes’ Debt to Beeckman’. In Descartes’ natural philosophy, ed. S. Gaukroger, J.A. Schuster, and J. Sutton, 46–59. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  6. Carteron, Henri. 1923. La Notion de force dans la système d’Aristote. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
  7. Clagett, Marshall. 1961. The science of mechanics in the middle ages. Madison: Wisconsin University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Cohen, H.Floris. 1984. Quantifying music: The science of music at the first stage of the scientific revolution. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  9. Duhem, Pierre. 1905–6. Les origines de la statique, 2 vols. Paris: A. Herman.Google Scholar
  10. Duhem, Pierre. 1906–13. Etudes sur Leonard de Vinci, 3 vols. Paris: A. Hermann. Google Scholar
  11. Garber, Daniel. 1992. Descartes’ metaphysical physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  12. Gaukroger, S. 1995. Descartes: An intellectual biography. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
  13. Gaukroger, S., and J.A. Schuster. 2002. The hydrostatic paradox and the origins of Cartesian dynamics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 33: 535–572.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Hanson, Norwood Russell. 1958. Patterns of discovery. Cambridge: CUP.Google Scholar
  15. Heeffer, A. 2006. The logic of disguise: Descartes’ discovery of the law of refraction. Historia Scientiarum 16: 144–165.Google Scholar
  16. Hooykass, R. 1981. Isaac Beeckman. In Dictionary of scientific biography, vol. 1, ed. C.C. Gillespie, 566–568. New York: Scribners.Google Scholar
  17. Jullien, Vincent, and André Charrak. 2002. Ce que dit Descartes touchant la chute des graves: De 1618 à 1646, étude d’un indicateur de la philosophie naturelle cartésienne Presses Universitaires du Septentrion.Google Scholar
  18. Kepler, Johannes. 1938ff. Gesammelte Werke, ed. M. Caspar. Munich: Beck.Google Scholar
  19. Knorr-Cetina, Karin. 1981. The manufacture of knowledge: An essay on the constructivist and conventional character of knowledge and cognition. Oxford: Pergamon.Google Scholar
  20. Koyré, A. 1939, Eng. Trans. 1978. Etudes Galiléennes. Paris: Hermann & Cie. English trans. Galileo Studies. Trans. J. Mepham. Hassocks, Sussex: Harvester.Google Scholar
  21. Laird, W.R. 1986. The scope of renaissance mechanics. Osiris 2: 43–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Latour, Bruno. 1987. Science in Action. Milton Keynes: Open University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Lindberg, David. 1968. The cause of refraction in medieval optics. British Journal for the History of Science 4: 23–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Mahoney, M.S. 1981. Petrus Ramus. In Dictionary of scientific biography, vol. 11, ed. C.C. Gillespie, 286–290. New York: Scribners.Google Scholar
  25. Mersenne, Marin. 1627. Traité de l’Harmonie universelle, 3 vols. Paris: Sebastien Cramoisy.Google Scholar
  26. Mersenne, M. 1932–88. Correspondence du P. Marin Mersenne, 17 vols, eds. C. de Waard, R. Pintard, B. Rochot, and A. Baelieu. Paris, Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique.Google Scholar
  27. Milhaud, Gaston. 1921. Descartes savant. Paris: Alcan.Google Scholar
  28. Ong, Walter S.J. 1958. Ramus: Method and the decay of dialogue. From the art of discourse to the art of reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Pickering, Andrew. 1995. The mangle of practice: Time, agency and science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  30. Pinch, Trevor. 1985. Towards an analysis of scientific observation: The externality and evidential significance of observational reports in physics. Social Studies of Science 15: 3–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Ravetz, J.R. 1971. Scientific Knowledge and its Social Problems. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
  32. Rodis-Lewis, Geneviève. 1971. L’Oeuvre de Descartes, 2 vols. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
  33. Rose, Paul Lawrence, and Stillman Drake. 1971. The Pseudo-Aristotelian Questions of Mechanics in renaissance culture. Studies in the Renaissance 18: 65–104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Rossi, Paolo. 1970. Philosophy, technology and the arts in the early modern era. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
  35. Sabra, A.I. 1967. Theories of light from Descartes to Newton. London: Oldbourne.Google Scholar
  36. Schuster, J.A. 1977. Descartes and the scientific revolution 1618–34: An interpretation, 2 vols, Unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, Princeton University.Google Scholar
  37. Schuster, J.A. 1980. Descartes’ Mathesis Universalis: 1619–28. In Descartes: Philosophy, mathematics and physics, ed. S. Gaukroger, 41–96. Sussex: Harvester.Google Scholar
  38. Schuster, J.A. 2000. Descartes Opticien: The construction of the law of refraction and the manufacture of its physical rationales, 1618-29. In Descartes’ natural philosophy, ed. S. Gaukroger, J.A. Schuster, and J. Sutton, 258–312. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  39. Schuster, J.A. 2005. Waterworld”: Descartes’ vortical celestial mechanics: A gambit in the natural philosophical contest of the early seventeenth century. In The science of nature in the seventeenth century: Changing patterns of early modern natural philosophy, ed. Peter Anstey and John Schuster, 35–79. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  40. Sepper, Dennis. 1996. Descartes’s imagination. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  41. Sepper, Dennis. 2000. Figuring things out: Figurate problem-solving in the early Descartes. In Descartes’ natural philosophy, ed. S. Gaukroger, J.A. Schuster, and J. Sutton, 228–248. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  42. Shea, W. 1991. The magic of motion and numbers: The scientific career of René Descartes. Canton: Science History Publications.Google Scholar
  43. Stevin, Simon. 1586. De Beghinselen des Waterwichts. Leiden, Inde druckerye van Christoffel Platin, by Françoyn van Raphelinghen.Google Scholar
  44. Stevin, Simon. 1955–66. The principal works of Simon Stevin, 5 vols, eds. Ernst Cronie et al. Amsterdam: Swets & Zeitlinger.Google Scholar
  45. Vollgraff, J.A. 1913. Pierre de la Ramée (1515–1572) et Willebrord Snel van Royen (1580–1626). Janus 18: 595–625.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Campion CollegeSydneyAustralia
  2. 2.Unit for History and Philosophy of ScienceUniversity of SydneySydneyAustralia

Personalised recommendations