Advertisement

What Do You Mean by “Redundancy”?

  • María José Frápolli
Chapter
Part of the Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science book series (LEUS, volume 29)

Abstract

When the name of Frank Ramsey is pronounced, one of the (few) things that come to everybody’s mind is the theory of truth as redundancy. In this section, we will argue that Ramsey never supported such a theory, but rather an analysis of truth noticeably similar to the prosentential account we are defending.

Keywords

Singular Term Propositional Content Propositional Variable Truth Predicate Expressive Character 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Austin, J. 1950. Truth. In Philosophical papers (1961), 126 y ss. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Bezuidenhout, A. 2004. Procedural meaning and the semantics/ pragmatics interface. In The semantics/pragmatics distinction, ed. C. Bianchi, 101–131. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  3. Blakemore, D. 1987. Semantic constraints on relevance. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  4. Blakemore, D. 1988. ‘So’ as a constraint on relevance. In Mental representations: The interface between language and reality, ed. R. Kempson, 183–195. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Blakemore, D. 1992. Understanding utterances. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  6. Brandom, R. 1994. Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Camós, F. 2008. Sinsentidos. Un análisis pragmático de los fracasos comunicativos. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Granada.Google Scholar
  8. Carston, R. 2002. Thoughts and utterances: The pragmatics of explicit communication. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Castañeda, H.N. 1966. A study in the logic of self-consciousness. In The phenomeno-logic of the I, ed. James G. Hart and Kapitan Tomis, 35–60. Bloomington/Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Castañeda, H.N. 1967. Indicators and quasi-indicators. In The phenomeno-logic of the I, ed. James G. Hart and Kapitan Tomis, 61–95. Bloomington/Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Frápolli, M.J. 2005a. Ramsey’s Theory of truth and the origins of the pro-sentential account. In F. P. Ramsey. Critical reassessments, ed. M.J. Frápolli, 113–138. London: Thoemmes Continuum.Google Scholar
  12. Kneale, W.C., and Martha Kneale. 1962. The development of logic. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  13. Künne, W. 2003. Conceptions of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Perry, J. 1979. The problem of essential indexical. Nous 13: 3–21. Also in Perry, 2000, 27–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Ramsey, F.P. 1927a. Facts and propositions. In Fundations. Essays in philosophy, logic, mathematics and economics, ed. D.H. Mellor, 40–57. London: Routledge/Kegan Paul. 1978, Also in Philosophical Papers. F.P.Ramsey. Ed. D.H.Mellor. Cambridge University Press, 34–51.Google Scholar
  16. Ramsey, F.P. 1927b/1991. The nature of truth. In On truth. Original manuscript materials (1927–1929) from the Ramsey collection at the University of Pittsburgh, ed. N. Rescher and U. Majer, 6–16. Dordrech: Kluwer Academic.Google Scholar
  17. Recanati, F. 2000. Oratio obliqua, oratio recta. An essay on metarepresentation. Cambridge, MA/London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  18. Recanati, F. 2007. Perspectival thought. A plea for (moderate) relativism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Rescher, N., and U. Majer (eds.). 1991. On truth. Original manuscript materials (1927–1929) from the Ramsey collection at the University of Pittsburgh. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.Google Scholar
  20. Stainton, R. 1994. Using non-sentences: An application of relevance theory. Pragmatics and Cognition 2: 269–284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Stainton, R. 1997. Utterance meaning and syntactic ellipsis. Pragmatics and Cognition 5: 51–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Stainton, R. 2006. Words and thoughts: Subsentences, ellipsis, and the philosophy of language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Strawson, P.F. 1950. Truth. In Truth. Oxford readings in philosophy, ed. Blackburn Simon and Simmons Keith, 162–182. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1999.Google Scholar
  24. van Benthem, J. 1984. Foundations of conditional logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic 13(3): 303–349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Villanueva Fernández, N., and de Brabanter, P. 2007. A linguistic road to epistemic deference. Paper given at the International Conference on Linguistics and Epistemology, University of Aberdeen, Scotland.Google Scholar
  26. Wilson, D. 1975. Presuppositions and non-truth-conditional semantics. New York: Academic.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  • María José Frápolli
    • 1
  1. 1.PhilosophyUniversity of GranadaGranadaSpain

Personalised recommendations