Skip to main content

A Paraconsistent and Substructural Conditional Logic

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Paraconsistency: Logic and Applications

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 26))

  • 1039 Accesses

Abstract

I introduce and motivate a conditional logic based on the substructural system HL from Paoli (Substructural logics: a primer, Kluwer, Dordrecht, 2002). Its hallmark is the presence of three logical levels (each one of which contains its own conditional connective), linked to one another by means of appropriate distribution principles. Such a theory brings about a twofold benefit: on the one hand, it yields a new classification of conditionals where the traditional dichotomies (indicative vs subjunctive, factual vs counterfactual) do not play a decisive role; on the other hand, it allows to retain suitable versions of both substitution of provable equivalents and simplification of disjunctive antecedents, while still keeping out such debatable principles as transitivity, monotonicity, and contraposition.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Observe that Weatherson is defending a substantially different theory in his more recent Weatherson (2009).

  2. 2.

    Of course we must rule out such pseudoconditionals as Austin’s “There are biscuits on the sideboard if you want some”. These sentences will not be considered further in this paper.

  3. 3.

    What about associativity? I do not have univocal intuitions either way. In my formal theory below, I will not assume that this property holds.

  4. 4.

    And, if the order of the disjuncts in the original disjunction had been reversed, the resulting conditional would instead have been acceptable simply in virtue of the fact that its main clause was taken for granted.

  5. 5.

    Do these conditionals actually occur in everyday speech? People often use conditionals like “If Pete is a good barber, then I’m a monkey’s uncle”. Nonetheless, they are often dismissed as mere rhetorical devices. It is remarked in Anderson and Belnap (1975), p. 163: “It is of course sometimes said that the ‘if-then’ we use admits that false or contradictory propositions imply anything you like, and we are given the example ‘If Hitler was a military genius, then I’m a monkey’s uncle’. But it seems to us unsatisfactory to dignify as a principle of logic what is obviously no more than rhetorical figure of speech, and a facetious one at that”. In my opinion, however, the decisive issue is not whether to dignify or not the ex absurdo quodlibet as a principle of logic: it is only that we must correctly determine for which logical constants it holds and for which ones it fails. “Monkey’s uncle” conditionals are commonly used by ordinary English speakers and have an “if…then” grammatical form; moreover, people freely use the ex absurdo quodlibet in dealing with these sentences. If it is thought that they are not proper hypotheticals, independent reasons should be given to justify this claim. I believe that the linguistic data do not lead to dispose of them offhand as pseudoconditionals—but, as long as they are conveniently kept distinct from conditionals which do not abide by that law, there is little to worry about. This issue, by the way, marks a first difference between my perspective and the relevant one (more will emerge soon): since the implicational paradoxes plainly fail for the relevant conditional, Anderson and Belnap conclude that they are fallacious altogether. On the contrary, I think that they are false of other kinds of conditionals but true of this one.

  6. 6.

    Advocates of the Gricean conversational account of paradoxes of material implication, like Lewis, will disagree: however, Read (1988) and others have convincingly shown that the recourse to implicature yields no advantage in the case of nested conditionals and wherever the conditional is not the principal connective of the sentence at issue. Therefore, it does not offer a viable solution to the paradoxes.

  7. 7.

    In the framework of standard possible world semantics, in fact, A > B would be true at w just in case f A (w) ⊆ [B]], while ¬B >  ¬A would be true at w just in case f ¬B (w) ⊆ [ ¬A]. Likewise, A⋎B would be true at w just in case f ¬A (w) ⊆ [B], while B⋎A would be true at w just in case f ¬B (w) ⊆ [A]. Obviously, these conditions need not be equivalent.

  8. 8.

    Caution: Anderson and Belnap use the horseshoe to denote both the classical conditional, which obeys modus ponens in any arbitrary theory, and the extensional conditional of their relevant logic, which does not. My chosen notation avoids any possible misunderstanding.

  9. 9.

    See again Paoli (2007) for a more detailed discussion of this point.

  10. 10.

    Anderson and Belnap are not the sole authors in the relevant tradition who seem committed to such an equivocation. Hunter (1993), for one, followed their lead. A happy exception is the paper Mares and Fuhrmann (1995), where the arrow is carefully distinguished from the corner, although the squiggle is assigned no special status.

  11. 11.

    The last statement is not always correct, though. Consider the perfectly grammatical disjunctive paraphrase of a subjunctive conditional: “I had to jot that down or I would have forgotten it” (Dowing 1975, p. 86).

  12. 12.

    Cp. the remark in Smiley (1984): “When a conditional conveys temporal succession […] it becomes an understatement to say that contraposition fails. Either the contraposed conditional conveys a message unrelated to the original (compare ‘If the surgeon didn’t operate the patient would die’ with ‘If the patient didn’t die the surgeon would operate’) or it fails to convey a coherent message at all (try contraposing ‘If the surgeon didn’t operate tonight the patient would die tomorrow’)”.

  13. 13.

    It suffices to consider any subjunctive conditional with the opt-out property: “If Oswald hadn’t killed Kennedy no one else would have”, indeed, does not seem to imply “If Oswald didn’t kill Kennedy no one else did”.

  14. 14.

    In most relevant logics, to be sure, distribution for extensional connectives is available, whereas it fails in linear logic and in Meyer (1966) LR, whose sequent version is obtained from the classical sequent calculus by dropping the rules of weakening. I argued in Paoli (2007) that nondistributive logics are the best motivated relevant logics.

  15. 15.

    I tried to keep my preference for a proof-conditional (over a truth-conditional) semantics for logical constants in the background but, as you see, I failed. Observe, however, that what I said so far is independent from such a personal liking. For a defence of this view, see Paoli (2007).

  16. 16.

    As it is customary to do in the tradition of abstract algebraic logic, I will not distinguish between logical languages and algebraic similarity types; therefore, I will use the same symbols for logical connectives and the corresponding operation symbols. Fm(£) will denote both the set of all formulas of £ (seen as a logical language) and the set of all terms of £ (seen as an algebraic similarity type), and likewise for Fm(£ ).

References

  • Adams, V.M. 1970. Subjunctive and indicative conditionals. Foundations of Language 6: 89–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allo, P. 2011. On when a disjunction is informative: Ambiguous connectives and pluralism. In The realism antirealism debate in the age of alternative logics, ed. S. Rahman et al., 1–23. Springer: Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alonso-Ovalle, L. 2008. Alternatives in the disjunctive antecedents problem. In Proceedings of the 26 west coast conference in formal linguistics, ed. C.B. Chang and H.J. Haynie, 42–50. Somerville: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, A.R., and N.D. Belnap. 1975. Entailment, vol I. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. 1988. Farewell to the phlogiston theory of conditionals. Mind 97: 509–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. 1995. Classifying conditionals: The traditional way is right. Mind 104: 331–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. 2003. A philosophical guide to conditionals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bryant, C. 1981. Conditional murderers. Analysis 41: 209–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casari, E. 1997. Conjoining and disjoining on different levels. In Logic and scientific methods, ed. M.L. Dalla Chiara et al., 261–288. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chellas, B. 1975. Basic conditional logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic 4: 133–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copeland, B.J. 1983. Pure semantics and applied semantics. Topoi 2: 197–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowing, P. 1975. Conditionals, impossibilities and material implication. Analysis 35: 85–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dudman, V.H. 1983. Tense and time in English verb clusters of the primary pattern. Australian Journal of Linguistics 3: 25–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dudman, V.H. 1984. Parsing ‘If’ sentences. Analysis 44: 145–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dudman, V.H. 1989. Vive la revolution. Mind 98: 591–603.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edgington, D. 1995. On conditionals. Mind 104: 235–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B., F. Jackson, and R. Pargetter. 1977. An objection to possible worlds semantics for counterfactual logics. Journal of Philosophical Logic 6: 355–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. 1975. Review of Lewis (1973). Mind 84: 451–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. 1981. Two recent theories of conditionals. In Ifs, ed. W.L. Harper et al., 211–247. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galatos, N., P. Jipsen, T. Kowalski, and H. Ono. 2007. Residuated lattices: An algebraic glimpse on substructural logics. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humberstone, L. 1978. Two merits of the circumstantial operator language for conditional logic. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 56: 21–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humberstone, L. 2011. The connectives. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunter, G. 1993. The meaning of ‘if’ in conditional propositions. Philosophical Quarterly 43: 279–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 1979. On assertion and indicative conditionals. Philosophical Review 88: 565–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 1987. Conditionals. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jansana, R. 201+. A course in abstract algebraic logic. e-notes available from the University of Barcelona website (Department of Philosophy).

    Google Scholar 

  • Klinedinst, N. 2007. Plurality and possibility. Ph.D. thesis, UCLA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1973. Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1976. Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities. Philosophical Review 85: 297–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. 1976. Counterfactuals with disjunctive antecedents. Journal of Philosophy 73: 531–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E.J. 1995. The truth about counterfactuals. Philosophical Quarterly 43: 41–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E. 2004. Relevant logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, R.K. 1966. Topics in modal and many-valued logics. Ph.D. thesis, University of Pittsburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, R.K. 1986. A farewell to entailment. RSSS research paper, ANU, Canberra.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E., and A. Fuhrmann. 1995. A relevant theory of conditionals. Journal of Philosophical Logic 24: 645–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nute, D. 1980. Topics in conditional logic. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nute, D. 1984. Conditional logic. In Handbook of Philosophical Logic, vol. II, ed. D. Gabbay and F. Guenthner, 387–439. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paoli, F. 2002. Substructural logics: A primer. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paoli, F. 2005. The ambiguity of quantifiers. Philosophical Studies 124: 313–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paoli, F. 2007. Implicational paradoxes and the meaning of logical constants. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85: 553–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. 2001. An introduction to non-classical logics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Read, S. 1988. Relevant logic. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Restall, G. 2000. An introduction to substructural logics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Routley, R., V. Plumwood, R.K. Meyer, and R.T. Brady. 1982. Relevant logics and their rivals. Atascadero: Ridgeview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sainsbury, M. 1991. Logical forms. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanford, D.H. 1989. If P then Q. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smiley, T. 1984. Hunter on conditionals. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 84: 113–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. 1968. A theory of conditionals. In Studies in logical theory, ed. N. Rescher, 98–112. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. 1975. Indicative conditionals. Philosophia 5: 269–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weatherson, B. 2001. Indicatives and subjunctives. Philosophical Quarterly 51: 200–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weatherson, B. 2009. Conditionals and indexical relativism. Synthese 166(2): 333–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

A version of the present paper was presented at the 4th World Congress on Paraconsistency (Melbourne, Australia, July 2008). I thank the audience of my talk for their stimulating questions and comments. I also thank Charlie Donauhe and an anonymous referee for their precious suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Francesco Paoli .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Paoli, F. (2013). A Paraconsistent and Substructural Conditional Logic. In: Tanaka, K., Berto, F., Mares, E., Paoli, F. (eds) Paraconsistency: Logic and Applications. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 26. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4438-7_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics