Skip to main content

Experimentation in the Natural Sciences

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover The Material Realization of Science

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 294))

Abstract

Commendable in Habermas is his explicit acknowledgment of the philosophical relevance of the process of experimentation in the natural sciences. In the philosophy of science, this experimental process is generally treated quite superficially, if it is discussed at all. Following Habermas, experimentation will also play a major role in the philosophical discussion of the next chapter. But before I can start with this we need a more accurate analysis (than Habermas provides) of experiment and experimentation in the natural sciences. I will give this analysis in the present chapter. In doing so, I distinguish three aspects: the theoretical-scientific description of experiments (Sect. 3.2); experimentation as action and materialization (Sect. 3.3); and the challenge the productive aspect of experimentation poses to realist interpretations of experimental science (Sect. 3.4).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Note that this expression is somewhat elliptical. In fact, p, p 1 , etc. always represent theoretical descriptions of experimental episodes, that is, propositions. For reasons of readability, I shall also speak of p and p 1 as “episodes” (except for cases in which this might lead to misunderstanding).

  2. 2.

    The concept of “reproducibility” will play a major role in my account of scientific experimentation. The present discussion is still rather sketchy. In what follows, I shall examine it on various occasions in more detail.

  3. 3.

    I therefore share Habermas’s view on this issue (see the last but one quotation in Sect. 1.4.1).

  4. 4.

    For a more extensive analysis of this example, see Koningsveld (1973, 87–100). In this context, see also Kuhn (1977b) and Barnes (1983).

  5. 5.

    This means, on the one hand, that several criticisms made against Von Wright (for instance, Tuomela 1978, 31–44; Bhaskar 1978, 54) do not apply to my account; on the other hand, it implies that my own criticism of Von Wright only applies to his claims regarding scientific experimentation.

  6. 6.

    Von Wright (1971, 63). For his reply to the question of the possibility of knowledge of nonmanipulable systems, see Von Wright (1971, 70–71).

  7. 7.

    “Reasonably”, for we can never be absolutely sure whether a 0 would not, of itself, have changed into a. We assume this as reasonable on the basis of earlier experiences. Von Wright argues that this “counterfactual” aspect (that certain things would not happen unless we do them and that other things would occur unless we prevent them) is an essential feature of the concept of human action.

  8. 8.

    For the definition, see Bhaskar (1978), 70; for the criticism, see Jongeling (1981, 29–40).

  9. 9.

    See also the distinction between isolated and closed systems in Prigogine and Stengers (1980, 134).

  10. 10.

    As the following example shows, these conditions may also be necessary for the experimental result itself, and not only, as Von Wright (1971, 63) states, for the carrying out of the experiment.

  11. 11.

    I do want to add that the essence of my criticism is not so much that necessary conditions should be included in addition to sufficient conditions. After all, Von Wright might accommodate this point by a slight (formal) modification of his definition of closedness. The main point of concern is that, generally speaking, not only the occurrence of the initial state requires active human intervention, but that this also holds true for the intermediate states and for the final state. Hence, an important objective of the entire analysis is to establish the exact meaning of the phrase that “in closed systems not only p, but also q has to be artificially produced”.

  12. 12.

    This means: sufficiently general within the context of this study. In other contexts, particularly those in which the social aspects of producing closed systems are prominent, we should also include the impact of the system on its surroundings. For this extension, see Radder (1986).

  13. 13.

    This implies developing an idea introduced in Radder (1978, 38–42).

  14. 14.

    Note that I use this example of Newtonian and Einsteinian mass, here and in the next chapter, only to indicate the philosophical problem (see also Kuhn 1970a, 101–102; Field 1973, 463–473). A much more detailed example will be provided in Chap. 5, in which I discuss the relation between the classical physical theories and quantum mechanics.

  15. 15.

    This study has been described quite extensively in Lynch et al. (1983, especially 225–229).

  16. 16.

    Compare also the distinction Harry Collins introduces between the “algorithmic” and the “enculturational” model for the replication of experiments (Collins 1975, 206–208).

  17. 17.

    There are, of course, exceptions. See, e.g., Hacking (1981, 1983).

  18. 18.

    See also Van Lieshout and Mol (1982, especially 30–61). They regard science as a constellation of “talk” (the verbal, the theoretical), “things” (the material) and “activities” (the social), in which these aspects are not hierarchically related but mutually structure each other. A striking example of ignoring the material dimension can be found in De Vries (1982). In his review of the book Laboratory Life, he leaves out completely the notion of materialization to which Bruno Latour and Steve Woolgar attach so much importance, and restricts himself to discussing their concept of “credibility”.

  19. 19.

    At least, in our modern culture. In Sect. 4.4, I will return to this important point.

  20. 20.

    Bhaskar (1982, 342). For what follows, see also Bhaskar (1978, 33–36, 53–56 and 255–262; 1979, 5–14). For a review of Bhaskar’s work, see Radder (1980).

  21. 21.

    Bhaskar (1982), 343. Thus, Bhaskar’s second argument implies a criticism of Habermas’s viewpoint with respect to technological application. While for Habermas a technology constitutes an extension of an experiment (as an “anticipated technology”), Bhaskar claims that there is a fundamental difference: in contrast with experimentation, technology generally takes place in basically open systems, where various contrary kinds of mechanisms operate simultaneously. It would carry us too far to subject this important disagreement between Habermas and Bhaskar to a closer examination, though I will briefly return to it in the Conclusion. For more on this subject, see Radder (1986).

References

  • Barnes, B. 1983. On the conventional character of knowledge and cognition. In Knorr-Cetina and Mulkay (1983), 19–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benton, T. 1981. Realism and social science. Some comments on Roy Bhaskar’s The Possibility of Naturalism. Radical Philosophy 27: 13–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. 1978. A realist theory of science, 2nd ed. Hassocks: Harvester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. 1979. The possibility of naturalism. A philosophical critique of the contemporary human sciences. Hassocks: Harvester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. 1982. Realism in the natural sciences. In Logic, methodology and philosophy of science, vol. VI, ed. L.J. Cohen et al., 337–354. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H.M. 1975. The seven sexes: A study in the sociology of a phenomenon, or the replication of experiments in physics. Sociology 9: 205–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Derksen, A.A. 1980. Rationaliteit en wetenschap. Assen: Van Gorcum.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Vries, G. 1982. De ontwikkeling van wetenschappelijke kennis, sociologisch beschouwd. Kennis en methode 6: 190–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. 1973. Theory change and the indeterminacy of reference. Journal of Philosophy 70: 462–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, Q. 1983. Tendencies. Philosophy of Science 50: 296–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. 1981. Spekulation, Berechnung und die Erschaffung von Phänomenen. In Versuchungen. Aufsätze zur Philosophie Paul Feyerabends, vol. 2, ed. H.-P. Duerr, 126–158. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. 1983. Representing and intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janich, P. 1978. Physics–Natural science or technology? In The dynamics of science and technology, ed. W. Krohn, E.T. Layton, and P. Weingart, 3–27. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jongeling, B. 1981. Bhaskar en de regelmatigheidsfilosofie. Research report, VU University, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koningsveld, H. 1973. Empirical laws, regularity and necessity. Wageningen: Veenman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. 1970a. The structure of scientific revolutions, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. 1977b. The function of measurement in modern physical science. In Essential tension, ed. T.S. Kuhn, 178–224. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B., and S. Woolgar. 1979. Laboratory life. The social construction of scientific facts. Beverly Hills: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lévy-Leblond, J.M. 1976. Ideology of/in contemporary physics. In The radicalisation of science. Ideology of/in the natural sciences, ed. H. Rose and S. Rose, 136–175. London: MacMillan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, M., E. Livingston, and H. Garfinkel. 1983. Temporal order in laboratory work. In Knorr-Cetina and Mulkay (1983), 205–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. 1967. The tacit dimension. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prigogine, I., and I. Stengers. 1980. Dialog mit der Natur. München: Piper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radder, H. 1978. Objektiviteit en waarheid in de kwantummechanika. In konfrontatie met Bohr en Habermas. Master’s thesis, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radder, H. 1980. Realisme in natuur- en menswetenschappen. Een bespreking van het werk van Roy Bhaskar. Krisis 2: 61–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radder, H. 1986. Experiment, technology and the intrinsic connection between knowledge and power. Social Studies of Science 16: 663–683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rip, A. 1982. The development of restrictedness in the sciences. In Scientific establishments and hierarchies, ed. N. Elias, H. Martins, and R. Whitley, 219–238. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. 1978. Erklären und verstehen menschlichen Verhaltens. In Neue Versuche über erklären und verstehen, ed. K.-O. Apel, J. Manninen, and R. Tuomela, 30–58. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Lieshout, P., and A. Mol. 1982. Aanzetten tot een kritiese wetenschapstheorie. Master’s thesis, Utrecht University, Utrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Wright, G.H. 1971. Explanation and understanding. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Radder, H. (2012). Experimentation in the Natural Sciences. In: The Material Realization of Science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 294. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4107-2_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics