Advertisement

The Buck-Passing Stops Here

  • Andrew MooreEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Studies in History and Philosophy of Science book series (AUST, volume 28)

Abstract

Thomas Scanlon influentially argues that, in the provision of reasons to act or believe, goodness and value ‘pass the buck’ to other properties. This paper first extends his arguments: if Scanlon shows that goodness and value pass the buck, then relevantly analogous arguments show that, contrary to Scanlon, duty and wrongness too pass this same buck. The paper then reverses Scanlon’s buck-passing arguments: if they show that goodness and value pass the reason-providing buck, then reasons themselves also pass the buck for providing goodness, value, duty, and wrongness. What to make of all this? The paper argues for scepticism about the significance of Scanlon’s buck-passing arguments for ethics.

Keywords

Ethical Consideration Ethical Theory Analogous Argument Ethical Matter Reversal Argument 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Notes

Acknowledgement

Conversations with Kent Hurtig started me on this paper. For comments on earlier drafts, I thank Martin Wilkinson, Jonas Olson, and Heather Dyke. Responses from participants at the Otago Philosophy Department seminar helped me to improve the paper. I thank James Maclaurin for leading the book project that this paper sits within. Above all, I thank Colin Cheyne – excellent philosopher, fine colleague and good friend.

References

  1. Crisp, R. 2005. Value, reasons, and the structure of justification: How to avoid passing the buck. Analysis 65(1): 80–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Dancy, J. 2000. Should we pass the buck? In The good, the true and the beautiful, ed. A. O’Hear, 159–173. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Hooker, B., and P. Stratton-Lake. 2006. Scanlon versus Moore on goodness. In Metaethics after Moore, ed. M. Timmons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Olson, J. 2004a. G.E. Moore on goodness and reasons. In Patterns of value: Essays on formal axiology and value analysis, Lund philosophy reports, vol. 2, ed. W. Rabinowicz and T. Ronnow-Rasmussen, 190–200. Lund: Department of Philosophy, Lund University.Google Scholar
  5. Parfit, D. 2001. Rationality and reasons. In Exploring practical philosophy: From action to values, ed. D. Egonnson, J. Josefsson, B. Petersson, and T. Ronnow-Rasmussen, 17–39. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  6. Scanlon, T. 1998. What we owe to each other. Harvard: Belknap.Google Scholar
  7. Scanlon, T. 2002. Reasons, responsibility, and reliance: Replies to Wallace, Dworkin, and Deigh. Ethics 112: 507–528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Scanlon, T. 2003. Replies. Ratio (new series) XVI (4 December): 424–439.Google Scholar
  9. Stratton-Lake, P. 2002. Introduction. In Ethical intuitionism: Re-evaluations, ed. P. Stratton-Lake. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  10. Stratton-Lake, P. 2003. Scanlon’s contractualism and the redundancy objection. Analysis 63(1): 70–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Timmons, M. 2002. Moral theory: An introduction. Lanham/Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of OtagoDunedinNew Zealand

Personalised recommendations