Advertisement

Literature and Truthfulness

  • Gregory Currie
Chapter
Part of the Studies in History and Philosophy of Science book series (AUST, volume 28)

Abstract

How should we characterise the view that we can learn about the mind from literature? Should we say that such learning consists in acquiring knowledge of truths? That option is more attractive than it is sometimes made to seem by those who oppose propositional knowledge to practical knowledge or “knowing how”. But some writers on this topic—Lamarque and Olsen—argue that, while literature may express interesting propositions, it is not their truth that matters, but their “content”. Matters to what? To literary criticism, they reply: there is no place in criticism for “debate about the truth or falsity of general statements about human life or the human condition.” I argue, to the contrary, that ideas of truth and truthfulness are woven into the fabric of a kind of criticism that is widespread now and comes with a long and distinguished history.

Keywords

Human Nature Positive View Literary Criticism Literary Work Literary Representation 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Bate, J. 2011. Review of Lupton: Thinking with Shakespeare. Times Higher Education, June 16. Retrieved 24 November 2011, from http://www.timeshighereducation.co.uk/story.asp?storycode=416504.
  2. Bevington, D. 2011. Murder most foul: Hamlet through the ages. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Christiansen, M.H., M.L. Kelly, R.C. Shillcock, and K. Greenfield. 2010. Impaired artificial grammar learning in agrammatism. Cognition 116: 382–393.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Devitt, M. 2011. Methodology and the nature of knowing how. Journal of Philosophy 108: 205–218.Google Scholar
  5. Devitt, M., and K. Sterelny. 1999. Language and reality. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  6. Djikic, M., K. Oatley, S. Zoeterman, and J.B. Peterson. 2009. On being moved by art: How reading fiction transforms the self. Creativity Research Journal 21(1): 24–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Doris, J. 2002. Lack of character: Personality and moral behavior. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Empson, W. 1951. The structure of complex words. London: Chatto & Windus.Google Scholar
  9. Gendler, T.S. 2010. Chapte3r 12, Imaginative contagion. In Intuition, imagination and philosophical methodology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Kivy, P. 1997. Philosophies of arts: An essay in differences. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Lamarque, P., and S. Olsen. 1994. Truth, fiction and literature. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Leavis, F.R. 1948. The great tradition: George Eliot, Henry James, Joseph Conrad. London: Chatto & Windus.Google Scholar
  13. Mar, R.A., K. Oatley, J. Hirsh, J. dela Paz, and J.B. Peterson. 2006. Bookworms versus nerds: Exposure to fiction versus non-fiction, divergent associations with social ability, and the simulation of fictional social worlds. Journal of Research in Personality 40: 694–712.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Mar, R.A., M. Djikic, and K. Oatley. 2008. Effects of reading on knowledge, social abilities, and selfhood. In Directions in empirical studies in literature: In honor of Willie van Peer, ed. S. Zyngier, M. Bortolussi, A. Chesnokova, and J. Auracher, 127–137. Amsterdam: Benjamins.Google Scholar
  15. Nussbaum, M. 1994. Love’s knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Robinson, J. 2005. Deeper than reason: Emotion and its role in literature, music, and art. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Snowden, P. 2003. Knowing how and knowing that: A distinction reconsidered. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 104: 1–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Stanley, J., and T. Williamson. 2001. Knowing how. Journal of Philosophy 98(8): 411–444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Taylor, D.J. 2011. Goosequill days. Times Literary Supplement, July 15, p. 15.Google Scholar
  20. Trilling, L. 1951. The liberal imagination. London: Secker and Warburg.Google Scholar
  21. Wilson, T. 2002. Strangers to ourselves: Discovering the adaptive unconscious. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Philosophy, Faculty of ArtsUniversity of NottinghamNottinghamUK

Personalised recommendations