Skip to main content

Time, Observables, and Structure

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science ((WONS,volume 77))

Abstract

In this chapter I consider what recent work on background independent physics can do for structuralism, and what structuralism can do for background independent physics. I focus on the problems of time and observables in gravitational physics. The ‘frozen’ character of the observables of general relativity is usually considered to constitute a serious problem for the theory. I argue that by invoking correlations between physical quantities we can provide a natural explanation of the appearance of time and change in timeless structures. I argue that this response can resolve a problem with Max Tegmark’s ‘extreme structuralist’ position. I then consider what bearing the mathematical representation used (namely Rovelli’s framework of ‘partial’ and ‘complete’ observables) has on the debate over the nature of structure in discussions of structural realism (i.e. the question of how structures are to be conceived). I argue that it has both the resources to ground the notion of structure in physics and to answer the ‘no relations without relata’ objection.

This chapter was originally written for the FQXi’s Nature of Time essay competition (http://www.fqxi.org/community/essay/winners/2008.1#Rickles). I thank FQXi for permission to reproduce the essay (albeit in modified form) here.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    As he puts it: ‘the mathematical formulation of the physicist’s often crude experience leads in an uncanny number of cases to an amazingly accurate description of a large class of phenomena’ [16, p. 230].

  2. 2.

    Though not all structural realists would go this far. Some, for example, would prefer to say that structure is physical, and that there might be biological and social structures that are not necessarily mathematical. However, the recent trends are towards extending structural realism across the entire domain of science, including biology [5] and economics [12]. The distinction between ‘physical’ and ‘mathematical,’ if it can be established at all, is not quite as simple as it might seem prima facie—see [8] for a discussion of this difficulty in the context of string theory.

  3. 3.

    For example, one can conceive of the laws being different, and indeed, as in David Lewis’ theory, the existence of a plurality of structures of the sort described can provide the machinery to ground such possibilities.

  4. 4.

    Related to this is the problem of equivalent mathematical structures that correspond to distinct physical situations. In other words, one and the same structure can be taken to represent very different systems. I don’t see this to be as problematic as it is sometimes taken to be. If there are indeed differences in the physical systems, then though we can indeed, in many cases, represent them using the same mathematical structure (for example, the Navier-Stokes equations can be applied to all manner of prima facie very different systems), that does not thereby mean that the systems would not have some other structures more closely corresponding to them. Any physical difference would simply mean that there ought to be a structural difference too, so long as we use a fine enough resolution of the structure.

  5. 5.

    To this we might add various geometric object fields representing the observed matter and radiation.

  6. 6.

    This view has been defended by a variety of authors; most notably Bryce DeWitt and Carlo Rovelli. Here I adopt Rovelli’s ‘partial’ and ‘complete’ observables formalism [13]. See [11] for a general review of the problem of time and proposed solutions.

  7. 7.

    I restrict the discussion to classical systems in order to make the presentation easier to follow. For the technically savvy, one can transform to the quantum case, roughly, by thinking of the functional relation or correlation \(\mathcal{A}(\mathcal{B})\) as representing the expectation values of \(\mathcal{A} \) relative to the eigenvalues of \(\mathcal{B} \).

  8. 8.

    It seems that Einstein might have been aware of this implication soon after completing his theory of general relativity, for he writes that ‘the connection between quantities in equations and measurable quantities is far more indirect than in the customary theories of old’ [4, p. 71].

  9. 9.

    There are two types of constraint in general relativity : the Hamiltonian (or scalar) constraint and the momentum (or vector) constraint. These can be understood as encoding indeterminacy about ‘when and where’ some quantity is measured.

  10. 10.

    There is a proof (for the case of closed vacuum solutions of general relativity) that there can be no local observables at all [15], where ‘local’ here means that the observable is constructed as a spatial integral of local functions of the initial data and their derivatives.

  11. 11.

    We might also call them ‘Kretschmann observables’ since they stem from Kretschmann’s objection to general covariance later incorporated into Einstein’s own ‘point-coincidence’ argument.

  12. 12.

    Once again, we find that Einstein was surprisingly modern-sounding on this point, writing that ‘the gravitational field at a certain location represents nothing “physically real”, but the gravitational field together with other data does’ [4, p. 71]. Likewise, the ‘other data’ will represent nothing without yet more data (such as the gravitational field). The correlations are the fundamental things.

  13. 13.

    Here then we have a clear answer to Chakravartty’s question ‘in what sense are relations more fundamental?’ (Chapter 10, p. 199). The physical weight is carried by the complete observables (the relational structures), and the partial observables (relata) are certainly not fundamental in the sense that they are not even physical but artefacts of the gauge choice employed.

References

  1. Dittrich, B. (2007) Partial and Complete Observables for Hamiltonian Constrained Systems. General Relativity and Gravitation 39: 1891–1927.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Earman, J. (2006) The Implications of General Covariance for the Ontology and Ideology of Spacetime. In D. Dieks (ed.), The Ontology of Spacetime (pp. 3–23). North Holland: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  3. Earman, J. (1921) A Generalisation of Weyl’s Theory of the Electromagnetic and Gravitational Fields. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series A 99(697): 104–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Einstein, E. (1918) Dialogue about Objections to the Theory of Relativity. In A. Engel (ed.), The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein (pp. 114–122), Vol. 7, The Berlin Years: Writings: 1918–1921, English Translation of Selected Texts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  5. French, S. (2011) Shifting to Structures in Physics and Biology: A Prophylactic for Promiscuous Realism. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biology and the Biomedical Sciences 42(2): 164–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Lewis, D.K. (1986) On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Montesinos, M., C. Rovelli, and T. Thiemann (1999) An \(\mathsf{SL (2 , \mathbb{R})}\) Model of Constrained Systems with two Hamiltonian Constraints. Physical Review D 60: 044009.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Rickles, D. (2010) Mirror Symmetry and Other Miracles in Superstring Theory. Foundations of Physics. Online First: DOI: 10.1007/s10701-010-9504-5.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Rickles, D. (2008) Who’s Afraid of Background Independence. In D. Dieks (ed.), The Ontology of Spacetime II (pp. 133–152). North Holland: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  10. Rickles, D. (2007) Symmetry, Structure, and Spacetime. North Holland: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Rickles, D. (2006) Time and Structure in Canonical Gravity. In D. Rickles, S. French, and J. Saatsi (eds.), The Structural Foundations of Quantum Gravity (pp. 152–195). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  12. Ross, D. (2008) Ontic Structural Realism and Economics. Philosophy of Science 75: 731–741.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Rovelli, C. (2002) Partial Observables. Physical Review D 65: 124013–124013–8.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Tegmark, M. (2006) The Mathematical Universe. Foundations of Physics 38: 101–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Torre, C. G. (1993) Gravitational Observables and Local Symmetries. Physical Review D 48: R2373–R2376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Wigner, E. P. (1967) The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences. In E. P. Wigner (ed.), Symmetries and Reflections: Scientific Essays (pp. 222–237). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dean P. Rickles .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rickles, D.P. (2012). Time, Observables, and Structure. In: Landry, E., Rickles, D. (eds) Structural Realism. The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, vol 77. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2579-9_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics