Skip to main content

Consensus Formation in Networked Groups

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: The European Philosophy of Science Association Proceedings ((EPSP,volume 1))

Abstract

This chapter proposes a solution, based on the theory of social networks, to the problem of weight assignment in the Lehrer-Wagner model for consensus. The Lehrer-Wagner model of consensus is introduced, and the problem of weight assignment is outlined, together with a number of possible solutions previously suggested in the literature. The chapter argues that there is no one-size-fits-all solution to the problem of weight assignment in the Lehrer-Wagner model, and suggests an alternative solution, which is based on the idea of deriving weights from existing networks of relations in the group. This proposal, it is argued, is particularly useful for maximizing or limiting the influence of a network of relations on the consensual opinion resulting from the model.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In Lehrer and Wagner (1981), the unqualified expression “matrix of weights” is at times used to refer to W.

  2. 2.

    P can contain other values, different from probabilities. Because this fact does not influence the considerations which will be made in the following sections, it will be ignored for the purposes of this chapter.

  3. 3.

    For a formal notion of reducibility see Meyer (2000, 209, 671) or Royle and Weisstein (2010).

  4. 4.

    The interested reader can refer to Goodin (2001), Lehrer (2001), and Bradley (2006) for some examples of the controversy.

  5. 5.

    Nurmi shows that the Leher-Wagner model, when weights are assigned subjectively, is manipulable (see Nurmi 1985, 15: Proposition 1).

  6. 6.

    Details on the function and derivation of weights are left to the interested reader (see Regan et al. 2006, 172).

  7. 7.

    See also Hegselmann and Krause (2005, 2006).

  8. 8.

    See Section 18.2, above, for the notion of reducibility. That this type of manipulation is possible can be seen from a look at the function for deriving weights in Regan et al. (2006, 172). The function is the following, \(w_{ij} = \frac{1 - | p_i - p_j|}{\sum_{j=1}^n 1 - | p_i - p_j|}\); when there are two agents in the model, giving each other weights, if i’s opinion is 1 and j’s opinion is 0, then w ij is indeterminate.

  9. 9.

    “Confidence interval” is used here in the sense of Hegselmann and Krause (2002), not to be confused with the homonymous concept used in statistics.

  10. 10.

    So far, I have taken both methods in Regan et al. (2006) and Hegselmann and Krause (2002) to be normative in character. Whereas the choice is not problematic for the former, it is arguable whether the latter should be taken as a normative model, at least in the authors’ intentions. In principle, however, there seems to be no reason for prohibiting that the Bounded Confidence model be taken normatively, regardless of the original authors’ intentions.

  11. 11.

    For a recent comprehensive treatment of networks in economics and sociology see Jackson (2008).

  12. 12.

    This case is exemplified in Fig. 18.2—see section 18.6.2—and will be treated in that section.

  13. 13.

    An agent is a “proximate neighbor” with another agent if there is an edge that connects them without passing through any other agent.

  14. 14.

    For an explanation of this see Hartmann et al. (2009, 120: Theorem 3)

  15. 15.

    Indeed early versions of consensus models that use the properties of convergent Markov chains make reference to DeGroot (1974), who takes the model to be descriptive in character. In fact, if the Lehrer-Wagner model is taken as an “impossibility of disagreement” result, as Lehrer (1976) does, it is necessary to take the model to be descriptively accurate, and not only rational from the normative view point. This point cannot be developed further in the space of this chapter.

References

  • Bradley, Richard. 2006. Taking advantage of difference in opinion. Episteme 3(3): 141–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeGroot, Morris. 1974. Reaching a consensus. Journal of the American Statistical Association 69: 118–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeMarzo, Peter M., Dimistri Vayanos, and Jeffrey Zwiebel. 2003. Persuasion bias, social influence and unidimensional opinions. The Quarterly Journal of Economics August: 909–968.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elga, Adam. 2007. Reflection and disagreement. Noûs 41(3): 478–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, John R.P. Jr. 1956. A formal theory of social power. Psychological Review 63(3): 181–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, Alvin. 1999. Knowledge in a social world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Golub, Benjamin, and Matthew O. Jackson. 2007. Naïve learning in social networks: Convergence, influence, and the wisdom of crowds. Working Papers Series FEEM Working Paper No. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, Robert E. 2001. Consensus interruptus. The Journal of Ethics 5: 121–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, Stephan, Carlo Martini, and Jan Sprenger. 2009. Consensual decision-making among epistemic peers. Episteme 6(2): 110–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hegselmann, Rainer, and Ulrich Krause. 2002. Opinion dynamics and bounded confidence: Models, analysis and simulation. Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation 5(3): 1–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegselmann, Rainer, and Ulrich Krause. 2005. Opinion dynamics driven by different ways of averaging. Computational Economics 25: 381–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hegselmann, Rainer, and Ulrich Krause. 2006. Truth and cognitive division of labour first steps towards a computer aided social epistemology. Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation 9(3): 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, Matthew O. 2008. Social and economic networks. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, Thomas. 2005. Peer disagreement and higher order evidence. In Oxford studies in epistemology—Volume 1, eds. John Hawthorne and Tamar Gendler Szabo, 167–196. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip. 1990. The division of cognitive labor. The Journal of Philosophy 87(1): 5–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, Keith. 1976. When rational disagreement is impossible. Noûs 10(3): 327–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, Keith. 2001. The rationality of dissensus: A reply to goodin. The Journal of Ethics 5: 133–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, Keith, and Carl Wagner. 1981. Rational consensus in science and society. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • List, Christian, and Philip Pettit. 2011. Group agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • List, Christian, and Robert E. Goodin. 2001. Epistemic democracy: Generalizing the condorcet Jury theorem. Journal of Political Philosophy 9: 277–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, Carl D. 2000. Matrix analysis and applied linear algebra. Philadelphia PA: Society for Industrial and Applied Mathematics (SIAM).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi, Hannu. 1985. Some properties of the Lehrer-Wagner method for reaching rational consensus. Synthese 62: 13–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Regan, Helen M., Mark Colyvan, and Lisa Markovchick-Nicholls. 2006. A formal model for consensus and negotiation in environmental management. Journal of Environmental Management 80: 167–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Royle, Gordon, and Eric W. Weisstein. 2010. Reducible Matrix. MathWorld—A Wolfram Web Resource. http://mathworld.wolfram.com/ReducibleMatrix.html—Retrieved 18 Feb 2010.

  • van Aaken, Anne, Christian List, and Christoph Luetge, eds. 2004. Deliberation and decision: Economics, constitutional theory and deliberative democracy. London: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, Carl. 1978. Consensus through respect: A model of rational group decision-making. Philosophical Studies 34: 335–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisstein, Eric W. 2011. Graph. MathWorld—A Wolfram Web Resource. http://mathworld.wolfram.com/Graph.html—Retrieved 10 Jan 2011.

  • Young, H.P. 1988. Condorcet’s theory of voting. American Political Science Review 82: 1231–1244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Carlo Martini .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this paper

Cite this paper

Martini, C. (2012). Consensus Formation in Networked Groups. In: de Regt, H., Hartmann, S., Okasha, S. (eds) EPSA Philosophy of Science: Amsterdam 2009. The European Philosophy of Science Association Proceedings, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2404-4_18

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics