Skip to main content

Realism and Reductionism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Interpreting Physics

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 289))

  • 1228 Accesses

Abstract

Philosophical discussions of many problems implicitly presuppose an interpretation of physics. This chapter considers the changes in four problematic issues consequent upon a change in the interpretation of physics. The first is continuity. Interpreting the language of classical physics as a specialized extension of an ordinary language core allows for an underlying continuity in the historical development of physics, rather than a series of paradigm shifts. The second problematic concerns realism. We distinguish the functional realism, implicit in ordinary language and its extensions, from theories concerning a correspondence with objective reality. Functional realism banks on public objects and is adequate to the practice of physics. The third problem area concerns emergence and reduction. Traditional global reductionism relies on a metaphysics that is an idealization of distinctive features of classical physics. Physics, as interpreted here, does not support the traditional program of global reductionism, but accepts reductionism as a default position between levels and allows the possibility of emergence. The final problem concerns the human order and the mind-body problem. We outline a way in which the human order, which has epistemological primacy, relates to the quantum order, which has ontological primacy.

Metaphysics is the finding of bad reasons for what we believe on instinct, but to find these reasons is no less an instinct.

F. H. Bradley, Appearance and Reality: An Essay in Metaphysics, p. x.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Penrose (2004) gives a very detailed account of the interplay of physical ideas and mathematical formulations in the development of physics and a brief summary of its significance in section 34.2.

  2. 2.

    Georgi (1993), Manohar (1996) and Kaplan (2005) present general accounts of effective field theory. The tower of theories is explored in Kane (2000, chap. 3). The philosophical significance of effective theories has been treated in Hartmann (2001), and Castellani (2002).

  3. 3.

    The ‘reasonable man’ became established in legal tradition chiefly through the influence of Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes See Menand (2001, p. 343). Liability for damages in tort cases involves presuppositions about the expectations a reasonable man would have and the precautions he would take.

  4. 4.

    A Companion to Continental Philosophy (Critchley et al. 1998) has 56 articles surveying the overall development. None of these treat physics or the type of information physics supplies.

  5. 5.

    Hacking (1983) shifted the realism debates from a focus on theories to a focus on experiments and the use of entities as tools. I believe that in functional scientific realism the emphasis should be on entities accepted as public objects, some of which may serve as experimental tools. Franklin (1981, 1983, 1986) and Galison (1987) emphasize the role of experimental traditions in setting up and interpreting experiments.

  6. 6.

    This simple labeling slights the subtlety of her neo-Kantian analysis. However her analysis, like Kant, slights the role of language in concept formation.

  7. 7.

    See Putnam (1987, 1990). Conant’s introduction to (1990) contains a survey of Putnam’s development as does Norris (1999) and Putnam (2004).

  8. 8.

    Fine’s NOA was developed in his (1986) and elsewhere.

  9. 9.

    Pinker (2007, pp. 208–225) analyzes primitive notions of causality reflected in dead or submerged metaphors operative in many different ordinary languages. The conjecture is that the primitive notion involved a conflict between an antagonist using force to change the natural state of an agonist. Hanson (1961, chap. 3) presented an influential argument against the extension of the ordinary notion of causality to scientific explanations.

  10. 10.

    Surveys of these developments may be found in Kim (1990), Moser and Trout (1995) and Block et al. (1997).

  11. 11.

    A more detailed account including these differences can be found in MacKinnon (2009).

  12. 12.

    Surprisingly, Thomas Aquinas set the methodology for conducting such arguments in an unprejudical fashion. In his methodology natural philosophy begins with the assumption that all beings are material beings and postulates non-material beings only if this proves inadequate. The reasons he found this assumption inadequate in explaining motion and concept formation are no longer viable.

  13. 13.

    John Searle’s New York Review article of March 6, 1997 led to an exchange between Chalmers and Searle, ibid, May 15, 1997, pp. 60–61.

  14. 14.

    See Tarlaci (2010) for an historical survey of attempts to invoke quantum mechanics in explaining brain processes.

  15. 15.

    Such a position has been developed in Bitbol (2007).

  16. 16.

    Churchland (1981), reproduced in many anthologies. When confronted with criticisms, such as the inconsistency involved in defending a belief that beliefs do not exist, he has broadened the status of folk psychology to a pervasive framework.

  17. 17.

    Her published article is available online at http://www.bbsonline.org/Preprints/Falk/Referees. It contains an extensive bibliography. Initial reactions are summarized in Scientific American, 291 (Aug. 2003, 30–32).

References

  • Auyang, Sunny. 1995. How is Quantum Field Theory Possible? New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bitbol, Michel. 2007. Ontology, matter and Emergence. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 293–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, Ned, Owen Flanagan, and Guven Guzeldere. 1997. The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broadfoot, S., U. Dorner, and D. Jaksh. 2009. Mixed State Entanglement Percolation. arXiv:0906/1622v1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, Nancy. 1983. How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Castellani, E. 2002. Reductionism, Emergence, and Effective Field Theories. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, B33, 251–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David, and John R. Searle. 1997. Consciousness and the Philosophers: An Exchange. The New York Review of Books, 44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, Patricia Smith. 1986. Neurophilosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, Paul. 1981. Eliminative Materialism and Propositional Attitudes. The Journal of Philosophy, 78, 67–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, Paul, and Patricia Churchland. 1998. On the Contrary Critical Essays, 1987–1997. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Critchley, Simon, William Ralph Schroeder, and Jay Bernstein. 1998. A Companion to Continental Philosophy. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1970. Mental events. In L. Foster, and J. Swanson (eds.), Experience and Theory. Humanities Press (pp. 79–101). Oxford: Reprinted in Essays on Action and Events (Oxford University Press, 1980).

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. 2001. Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective. Oxford: Calarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel. 2003. Freedom Evolves. New York, NY: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel. 2009. Intentional Systems Theory. In B. McLaughlin, A. Beckermann, and S. Walter, (eds.), Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Falk, Dean. 2003. Prelinguistic Evolution in Early Homins: Whence motherese? Behaviorall and Brain Science, 27, 491–534.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, Herbert. 1958. The ‘Mental’ and the ‘Physical’. In Herbert Feigl, Michael Scriven, and Grover Maxwell (eds.), Minnesoat Studies in the Philosophy of Science (pp. 370–497). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, Arthur. 1986. The Shaky Game. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, Alan. 1981 What Makes a Good Experiment. British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 32, 367–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, Allan. 1983. The Discovery and Acceptance of CP Violation. Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, 13, 207–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, Alan. 1986. The Neglect of Experiment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Galison, Peter. 1987. How Experiments End. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Georgi, Howard. 1993. Effective Field Theory. Annual Review of Nuclear Physics, 43, 209–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, Carl. 2007. The New Reductionism. The Journal of Philosophy, 104, 193–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, Clark. 2007. When is a Brain Like the Planet? Philosophy of Science, 74, 330–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, Ian. 1983. Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, Ian. 1991. A Tradition of Natural Kinds. Philosophical Studies, 51, 109–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, Ian. 2009. Natural Kinds: Rosy Dawn, Scholastic Twilight. Address to the Bay Area Philosophy of Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hameroff, S. R., and R. Penrose 1996. Conscious Events as Orchestrated Space-Time Selections. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3, 36–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, Norwood Russell. 1961. Patterns of Discovery: An Inquiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science. Cambridge Eng.: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A., and Antony Maurice Honoré. 1959. Causation in the Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, S. 2001. Effective Field Theories, Reductionism and Scientific Explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 32B, 267–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphrey, Paul. 1997. How Properties Emerge. Philosophy of Science, 64, 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Kent. 2004. On the Systematicity of Language and Thought. The Journal of Philosophy, 101, 111–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kane, Gordon. 2000. Supersymmetry. Cambridge, MA: Perseus Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, David. 2005. Five Lectures on Effective Field Theory. arXiv:nucl-th/0510023v1, arXiv:nucl-th/0510023.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, Anthony. 1992. The Metaphysics of Mind. Oxford, England; New York, NY: Oxford University Press; Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, Jaegwon. 1982. Psychophysical Supervenience. Philosophical Studies, 41, 51–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, Jaegwon. 1990. Supervenience as a Philosophical Concept. Metaphilosophy, 21, 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, Jaegwon. 1993. Supervenience and Mind: Selected Philosophical Essays. Cambridge, England, New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, Jaegwon. 1996. Philosophy of Mind. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, Jaegwon. 1998. Mind in a Physical World an Essay on the Mind-Body Problem and Mental Causation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, Jaegwon. 2002. Supervenience. Aldershot, Hants, England; Brookfield, VT: Ashgate; Dartmouth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, James. 1998. Structural Realism: Epistemology or Metaphysics? Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 409–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David. 1999. Psychophysical and Theoretical Identifications. In David Lewis (ed.), Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology (pp. 248–261). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • London, Fritz, and Edmund Bauer. 1983 [1939]. The Theory of Observation in Quantum Mechanics. In J. Wheeler, and W. Zurek (eds.), Quantum Theory and Measurement (pp. 217–259). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKinnon, Edward. 2009. The New Reductionism. The Philosophical Forum, 34, 439–462.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manohar, Aneesh. 1996. Effective Field Theories. arXiv:hep-ph/96061222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menand, Louis. 2001. The Metaphysical Club. New York, NY: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1945. Phénoménologie de la perception. Paris: Librairie Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moser, Paul, and J. D. Trout. 1995. General Introduction: Contemporary Materialism. In Moser Paul, and J. D. Trout (eds.), Contemporary Materilism (pp. 1–35). London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Ernest. 1961. The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation. New York, NY: Harcourt, Brace & World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, Christopher. 1999. Putnam’s Progress. The Philosophical Forum, 30, 61–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, Timothy. 1994. Emergent Properties. American Philosophical Quarterly, 31, 91–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, Timothy, and Jonathan Jacobs. 2003. Emergent Individuals. The Philosophical Quarterly, 33, 540–555.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheim, Paul, and Hilary Putnam. 1958. Unity of Science as a Working Hypothesis. In Herbert Feigl, Michael Scriven, and Grover Maxwell (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science: Volume II. Concepts, Theories, and the Mind-Body Problem (pp. 3–36). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, Roger. 2004. The Road to Reality: A Complete Guide to the Laws of the Universe. New York, NY: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, Steven. 2007. The Stuff of Thought: Language as a Window into Human Nature. New York, NY: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, Stathis. 2000. The Present State of the Scientific Realism Debate. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51, 705–728.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Hilary. 1987. The Many Faces of Realism. La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Hilary. 1990. Realism with a Human Face. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Hilary. 2004. Ethics Without Ontology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. 1983. Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. 1997. Consciousness and the Philosophers: An Exchange. The New York Review of Books, 44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. 1998. Mind, Language and Society: Philosophy in the Real World. New York, NY: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt, Johanna. 2002. Quanta, Tropes, or Processes: Ontologies for QFT Beyond the Myth of Substance. In Meinrad Kuhlmann, et al. (eds.), Ontological Aspects of Quantum Field Theory. Singapore: World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silberstein, Michael, and John McGeever. 1999. The Search for Ontological Emergence. The Philosophical Quarterly, 49, 182–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C. 1963. Philosophy and Scientific Realism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stapp, Henry. 1996. The Hard Problem: A Quantum Approach. Lawrence Berkeley Lab, LBL-37163.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stapp, Henry. 2007. Quantum Approaches to Consciousness. In Max Velmans, and Susan Schneider (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, Daniel. 2001. Physicalism. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Striano, T., and M. Tomasello. 2001. Infant Development: Physical and Social Cognition. In N. J. Smelsen, and P. B. Bate (eds.), International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences (pp. 7410–7414). Oxford: Pergamon.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tarlaci, Sultan. 2010. A Historical View of the Relation Between Quantum Mechanics and the Brain. Neuroquantology, 8, 120–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teller, Paul. 1995. An Interpretive Introduction to Quantum Field Theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, Bas. 1991. Quantum Mechanics: An Empiricist View. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, Bas. 2002. Structure: Its Shadow and Substance. Philosophy of Science Archives, 63.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, John. 1955 [1927]. Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, trans. Robert T. Beyer. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, Steven. 2008. Cosmology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, Eugene P. 1967. Symmetries and Reflections: Scientific Essays. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wooldridge, Dean E. 1966. The Machinery of Life. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, John. 1989. Structural Realism: The Best of Both Worlds. Dialectica, 43, 99–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Edward Mackinnon .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mackinnon, E. (2012). Realism and Reductionism. In: Interpreting Physics. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 289. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2369-6_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics