Advertisement

Fetal Pains and Fetal Brains

  • A.A. HowsepianEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Philosophy and Medicine book series (PHME, volume 111)

Abstract

There has been a groundswell of recent scholarship on the question of whether or when unborn humans become capable of feeling pain.1 (Anand and Hickey, 1987; Colette, 2003; Commission of Inquiry into Fetal Sentience, 1996; Derbyshire, 2006, 2008; Glover, 1999; Glover and Fisk, 1996; Kolenc, 2006; Lagercrantz and Changeux, 2009; Lee, Ralston and Drey et al., 2005; Lowery, Hardman and Manning et al., 2007; Mellor, Diesch, Gunn and Bennet, 2005; McCullagh, 1997; Myers, 2006; Royal College of Obstetricians and Gynaecologists, 2010; Saunders, 1997; Savell, 2007; Sonfield, 2005; Stahle, 2007; and Wenger, 2006, among others.) The reason for this rapidly growing literature is not difficult to discern: if unborn human beings are capable of feeling pain, this fact would have potentially enormous implications for how unborn humans ought to be treated, whether in the context of fetal surgery, embryonic and fetal experimentation,2 or induced abortion (hereafter, ‘abortion’). At least for the time being, the practical issues concerning fetal surgery and fetal experimentation have been largely settled. In the first instance, whether or not fetuses are capable of feeling pain while undergoing surgical procedures, not providing anesthesia during fetal surgery appears to have enough other untoward (stress-related and behavioral) effects on the fetus that anesthetizing human fetuses who are undergoing surgery (thanks, primarily, to the work of Anand, Sippel and Aynsley-Green, 1987) has quickly become the standard of care. In the second instance, potentially destructive research on unborn humans has, thus far, only seriously been entertained in very early human embryos that, everyone agrees (or at least everyone should agree), are too young to feel pain. The primary issue, therefore, currently controlling this discussion concerning fetal pain sentience is the issue of abortion. Because methods devised for killing unborn humans include some (e.g., ripping, scraping, burning, breaking, crushing, poisoning, and cutting) that might elicit pain in those beings on whom these methods of killing are employed, the question concerning whether or when human fetuses can feel pain has become a matter of significant clinical, ethical, and, more recently, legal urgency.3 (Collett, 2003; Stahle, 2007)

Keywords

Pain Experience Pain Perception Noxious Stimulus Emotional Content Pain Sentience 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Alkire, M.T., A.G. Hudetz, and G. Tononi. (7 November 2008). Consciousness and anesthesia. Science 322(5903): 876–880.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. All Party Parliamentary Pro-Life Group. (November 1996). Foetal sentience. Catholic Medical Quarterly XLVII (2): 6–12.Google Scholar
  3. Anand, K.J.S, and P.R. Hickey. 1987. Pain and its effects in the human neonate and fetus. New England Journal of Medicine 317: 1321–1329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Anand, K.J.S., W.G. Sippel, and A. Aynsley-Green. 1987. Randomized trial of fentanyl anesthesia in preterm babies undergoing surgery: Effects on the stress response. Lancet 1: 243–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Anand, K.J.S., and K.D. Craig. 1996. New perspectives on the definition of pain. Pain 67: 3–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Andrews, K., L. Murphy, R. Munday, and C. Littlewood. 1996. Misdiagnosis of the vegetative state: retrospective study in a rehabilitation unit. British Medical Journal 313: 13–16.Google Scholar
  7. Baron-Cohen, S. 1991. Precursors to a theory of mind: Understanding attention in others. In Natural theories of mind: Evolution, development and simulation of everyday mindreading, ed. A. Whiten, pp. 233–251. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  8. Benatar, D., and M. Benatar. 2001. A pain in the fetus: Toward ending confusion about fetal pain. Bioethics 15(1): 57–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Boly, M., M.-E. Faymonville, and P. Peigneux. 2004. Auditory processing in severely brain injured patients: Differences between the Minimally Conscious State and the Persistent Vegetative State. Archives of Neurology 61(2): 233–238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Brooks, J.C., L. Zambreanu, A. Godinez, et al. 2005. Somatotopic organization of the human insula to painful heat studied with high resolution functional imaging. Neuroimage 27: 201–209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Collett, T.S. 2003. Fetal pain legislation: Is it viable? Pepperdine Law Review 30: 161–184.Google Scholar
  12. Commission of Inquiry into Fetal Sentience. 1996. Human sentience before birth. Rawlison Report. London: HMSO.Google Scholar
  13. Craig, A.D. 2003. Interoception: The sense of the physiological condition of the body. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 13: 500–505.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Derbyshire, S.W. 1999. Locating the beginnings of pain. Bioethics 13: 1–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Derbyshire, S.W.G. (15 April 2006). Can fetuses feel pain? British Medical Journal 332: 909–912.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Derbyshire, S.W.G. 2008. Fetal pain: do we know enough to do the right thing? Reproductive Health Matters 16(31 supplement): 117–126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Fiser, K.B. 1986. Privacy and pain. Philosophical Investigations 9(1): 1–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Fitzgerald, M. 1987. Pain and analgesia in neonates. Trends in Neuroscience 10: 344–346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Fitzgerald, M. 2000. Development of peripheral and spinal pain systems. In Pain in neonates, eds. K.J.S. Anand, B.J. Stevens, and P.J. McGrath, 9–22. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  20. Fonagy, P., G. Gergely, E. Jurist, and M. Target. 2002. Affect regulation, mentalization, and the development of the self. New York, NY: Other Press.Google Scholar
  21. Glover, V., and N. Fisk. 1999. Fetal pain: Implications for research and practice. British Journal of Obstetrics and Gynaecology 106: 881–886.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Glover, V., and N. Fisk. (28 September 1996). We don’t know; Better to err on the safe side from mid-gestation. British Medical Journal 313(7060): 796.Google Scholar
  23. Howsepian, A.A. 1994. Philosophical reflections on coma. Review of Metaphysics 47(4): 735–755.Google Scholar
  24. Howsepian, A.A. 1996. The 1994 multi-society task force on the persistent vegetative state: A critical analysis. Issues in Law and Medicine 12(1): 3–29.Google Scholar
  25. Howsepian, A.A. 2006. Ethical, medical, and theological perspectives on those in ‘vegetative’ and other hypokinetic states. Christian Research Journal 29(1): 31–41.Google Scholar
  26. Howsepian, A.A. 2008. Four queries concerning the metaphysics of early human embryogenesis. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 33: 140–157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Howsepian, A.A. (2011). Consciousness and aesthetics in decisions concerning organ donation in anencephalic neonates. In The ethics of organ transplantation, ed. Steven J. Jensen, 72–91. Washington, DC: Catholic University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Humphrey, T. 1964. Some correlations between the appearance of human fetal reflexes and the development of the nervous system. Progress in Brain Research 4: 93–133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. International Association for the Study of Pain (IASP). “Pain” http://www.iasp-pain.org/AM/Template.cfm?Section=Pain_Defisplay.cfm&ContentID=1728#Pain. Accessed 13 Apr 2011.
  30. James, D. 1998. Fetal medicine. British Medical Journal 316: 158–1583.Google Scholar
  31. Kaufman, R. 1985. Is the concept of pain incoherent? Southern Journal of Philosophy 23: 279–284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Kinney, H.C., J. Korein, A. Panigraphy, et al. 1994. Neuropathological findings in the brain of Karen Quinlan. New England Journal of Medicine 330: 1469–1475.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Kohut, H. 1977. The restoration of the self. New York, NY: International Universities Press.Google Scholar
  34. Kolenc, A.B. 2006. Easing abortion’s pain: Can fetal pain legislation survive the new judicial scrutiny of legislative fact-finding? Texas Review of Law and Politics 11: 171–228.Google Scholar
  35. Lagercrantz, H., and J.-P. Changeux. 2009. The emergence of human consciousness: From fetal to neonatal life. Pediatric Research 65(3): 255–260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Lee, S.L., H.J.P. Ralston, E.A. Drey, et al. 2005. Fetal pain: A systematic multidisciplinary review of the evidence. Journal of the American Medical Association 294: 947–954.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Leventhal, H. 1984. A perceptual-motor theory of emotion. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 17: 117–175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Lewin, R. 1980. Is your brain really necessary? Science 210: 1232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Lowery, C.L., M.P. Hardman, N. Manning, et al. 2007. Neurodevelopmental changes of fetal pain. Seminars in Perinatology 31: 275–282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Manfredi, M., G. Bini, G. Cruccu, et al. 1981. Congenital absence of pain. Archives of Neurology 38(8): 507–511.Google Scholar
  41. McCullagh, P. (25 January 1997). Do fetuses feel pain? Can fetal suffering be excluded beyond reasonable doubt? British Medical Journal 314(7076): 302–303.Google Scholar
  42. Mellor, D.J., T.J. Diesch, A.J. Gunn, and L. Bennet. 2005. The importance of ‘awareness’ for understanding fetal pain. Brain Research Reviews 49: 455–471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Merker, B. 2007. Consciousness without a cerebral cortex: A challenge for neuroscience and medicine. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30: 63–134.Google Scholar
  44. Myers, L.B. (11 January 2006). Fetal pain. Journal of the American Medical Association [letter] 295(2): 159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Nagel, T. 1974. What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review 83(4): 435–450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Nandi, D., T. Aziz, H. Carter, et al. 2003. Thalamic field potentials in chronic central pain treated by periventricular gray stimulation: A series of eight cases. Pain 101: 97–107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Nandi, D., X. Liu, C. Joint, et al. 2002. Thalamic field potentials during deep brain stimulation of periventriular gray in chronic pain. Pain 97: 47–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Noren, S.J. 1974. Pitcher on the awfulness of pain. Philosophical Studies 25: 117–122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Penfield, W. 1952. Epileptic automatisms and the centrencephalic integrating system. Research Publication of the Association for Nervous and Mental Disease 30: 513–528.Google Scholar
  50. Penfield, W., and E. Bolder. 1937. Somatic motor and sensory representations in the cerebral cortex of man as studied by electrical stimulation. Brain 60: 389–443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Penfield, W., and H.H. Jasper. 1954. Epilepsy and the functional anatomy of the human brain. New York, NY: Little Brown.Google Scholar
  52. Plantinga, Alvin. 1967. God and other minds. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  53. Rokyta, R. 2008. Fetal pain. Neuroendocrinology Letters 29: 807–814.Google Scholar
  54. Royal College of Obstetricians and Gynaecologists. (March 2010). Fetal awareness: review of research and recommendations for practice: Report of a working party.Google Scholar
  55. Sacred Congregation of the Doctrine of the Faith. (1974, November 18). Declaration on Procured Abortion. Available:http://www.vatican.va/roman_curia/congregations/cfaith/documents/rc_con_cfaith_doc_19741118_declaration-abortion_en.html. Accessed 8 Feb 2011.
  56. Saunders, P.J. (25 January 1997). Do fetuses feel pain? We should give them the benefit of the doubt. [Letter] British Medical Journal 314(7076): 303.Google Scholar
  57. Savell, K.L. 2007. Life and death before birth: 4D ultrasound and the shifting frontiers of the abortion debate. Journal of Law and Medicine 15(1): 103–116.Google Scholar
  58. Shewmon, D.A. (Oct–Nov 1988). Anencephaly: Selected medical aspects. Hastings Center Report 18(5): 11–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Shewmon, D.A., A.M. Captron, W.J. Peacock, and B.L. Schulman. 1989. The use of anencephalic infants as organ sources. The Journal of the American Medical Association 261: 1773–1781.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Shewmon, D.A., G.L. Holmes, and P.A. Byrne. 1999. Consciousness in congenitally decorticate children: ‘Developmental vegetative state’ as self-fulfilling prophecy. Developmental Medicine and Child Neurology 41: 364–374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Sonfield, A. 2005. The uses and abuses of science in sexual and reproductive health policy debates. The Guttmacher Report on Public Policy (November): 1–3.Google Scholar
  62. Stahle, H. 2007. Fetal pain legislation: An undue burden. Quinnipiac Health Law Journal 10: 251–316.Google Scholar
  63. Strawson, P.F. 1959. Individuals: An essay in descriptive metaphysics. London: Methuen.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Tye, M. 1984. The adverbial approach to visual experience. The Philosophical Review 93(2): 195–225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Waxman, S.G. 2000. Correlative neuroanatomy, 24th ed. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
  66. Wenger, A.A. 2006. Fetal pain legislation: Subordinating sound medical findings to moral and political agendas. Journal of Legal Medicine 27: 459–476.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Fresno Medical Education Program, Department of PsychiatryUniversity of CaliforniaSan Francisco, FresnoUSA

Personalised recommendations