Abstract
The notion of preference arises from comparisons of alternatives. To formalize such comparisons and study them, there are two ways to go. We can represent preference in terms of qualitative binary relations, as we did in our modeling in Chapter 3, following a long logical tradition ([83, 100, 122] and [92]). Or we can introduce a utility or evaluation function which will assign values to the alternatives being compared. The latter quantitative method has been dominant in many research areas, e.g., game theory and social choice theory (cf. [74, 113, 114] and [63]).
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.
Buying options





Notes
- 1.
This position was held by famous utilitarians such as Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) and John Stuart Mill (1806–1876). It has even been claimed that this position is found millennia earlier in China with Mozi.
- 2.
A well-known result is that a preference relation that is complete, reflexive, transitive and continuous can be represented by a continuous utility function. In this chapter, we only consider representable preferences.
- 3.
We will discuss deontic applications in much greater detail in Chapter 11.
- 4.
In [10] the range is natural numbers up to a maximal element (Max). The values are normalized to Max. For me the distance between the numbers seems essential, so normalization is not an option. Similarly I like to be able to subtract unrestrictedly.
- 5.
Let us look at the relation between \(\mathcal{L}_{A}\) and \(\mathcal{L_E} \). From \(\mathcal{L}_{A}\) to \(\mathcal{L_E} \), we can define a translation: a formula of the form \(B^{m}\varphi\) is translated into \(K(q^{m}\rightarrow \varphi)\). This is to say that in the language \(\mathcal{L_E} \), we can express the same notions as [10] without introducing additional belief operators. This advantage leads to the much simpler completeness proof we will see. It becomes even more prominent when constructing reduction axioms for dynamics in the later sections. On the other hand, we can easily translate \(\mathcal{L_E} \) back into \(\mathcal{L}_A\): q m will be \(\neg B^m\bot\), which means that \(\mathcal{L}_{A} \) and \(\mathcal{L_E} \) are equivalent.
- 6.
The main reason why this argument can remain so simple, compared to earlier numerical systems, is our use of propositional constants for values of worlds.
- 7.
Actually, there are two different plausible interpretations here. One either thinks of the event as a command to change one’s evaluation of some current state, or as something which itself has a value that leads to a prescribed value change in the world where the event takes place.
- 8.
Other numerical rules are possible, but most of our later points would apply then as well.
- 9.
In practice, one will normally choose a small natural number, say, between 0 and 10, to denote the reliability or the relative force.
- 10.
The conditions for the epistemic relations ∼ are omitted, as they are routine.
- 11.
This also makes immediate sense in a multi-agent context, employing relative forces. One agent a may take the boss’s commands seriously, whereas agent b may not.
- 12.
Another relevant approach are the DEL models for trust developed in [109].
- 13.
This is closer to Veltman’s intuition that worlds are ordered by how many stated regularities they have satisfied in a longer discourse.
- 14.
As for a comparison with the dynamic semantics for defaults in [192], I suspect that the latter can be embedded into DEEL, but not vice versa.
References
Åqvist, L. 1994. Deontic logic. In Handbook of philosophical logic, eds. D. Gabbay and F. Guenthner, volume 2, 605–714. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Aucher, G. 2003. A combined system for update logic and belief revision. Master’s thesis, MoL-2003-03. ILLC, University of Amsterdam.
Balbiani, P., V. Goranko, R. Kellerman, and D. Vakarelov. 2007. Logical theories for fragments of elementary geometry. In Handbook of spatial logics, eds. M. Aiello, I. Pratt-Hartmann, and J. van Benthem, 343–428. Springer: Dordrecht.
Baltag, A., L.S. Moss, and S. Solecki. 1998. The logic of common knowledge, public announcements, and private suspicions. In Proceedings of the 7th conference on theoretical aspects of rationality and knowledge (TARK 98), ed. I. Gilboa, 43–56. Morgan Kaufmann Publishers: San Francisco, CA, USA.
van Benthem, J., J. Gerbrandy, and B. Kooi. 2009. Dynamic update with probabilities. Studia Logica 93(1):67–96.
van Benthem, J., and F. Liu. 2007. Dynamic logic of preference upgrade. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logic 17:157–182.
Coulhon, T., and P. Mongin. 1989. Social choice theory in the case of von neumann-morgenstern utilities. Soc Choice Welfare 6:175–187.
van Ditmarsch, H., W. van der Hoek, and B. Kooi. 2007. Dynamic epistemic logic. Berlin: Springer.
Fishburn, P.C. 1970. Utility theory for decision making. Huntington, NY: Robert E. Krieger Publishing Company.
Girard, P. 2008. Modal logics for belief and preference change. PhD thesis, Stanford University.
Grune-Yanoff, T., and S.O. Hansson. eds. 2009. Preference change: Approaches from philosophy, economics and psychology. Theory and Decision Library. Springer: Heidelberg.
Hansson, S.O. 1992. Similarity semantics and minimal changes of belief. Erkenntnis 37:401–429.
Hansson, S.O. 1995. Changes in preference. Theory and Decision 38:1–28.
Holliday, W.H. 2009. Dynamic testimonial logic. In Proceedings of the 2nd international workshop on logic, rationality, and interaction (LORI 2009), eds. X. He, J. Horty, and E. Pacuit, volume 5834 of FoLLI-LNAI, 161–179. Springer: Heidelberg.
Jeffrey, R.C. 1965. The logic of decision. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Jeffrey, R.C. 1977. A note on the kinematics of preference. Erkenntnis 11:135–141.
Lang, J., and L. van der Torre. 2008. From belief change to preference change. In Proceedings of the 18th European conference on artificial intelligence (ECAI-2008), 351–355. IOS Press: Amsterdam.
Liu, F. 2004. Dynamic variations: Update and revision for diverse agents. Master’s thesis, MoL-2004-05. ILLC, University of Amsterdam.
Liu, F. 2009. Diversity of agents and their interaction. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 18(1):23–53.
van der Meyden, R. 1996. The dynamic logic of permission. Journal of Logic and Computation 6:465–479.
Meyer, J.-J.Ch. 1988. A different approach to deontic logic: Deontic logic viewed as a variant of dynamic logic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 29:109–136.
Spohn, W. 1988. Ordinal conditional functions: A dynamic theory of epistemic states. In Causation in decision, belief change and statistics II, eds. W.L. Harper and B. Skyrms, 105–134. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
van der Torre, L. and Y. Tan. 1999. An update semantics for deontic reasoning. In Norms, logics and information systems, eds. P. McNamara and H. Prakken, 73–90. Amsterdam: IOS Press.
Veltman, F. 1996. Defaults in update semantics. Journal of Philosophical Logic 25:221–261.
Williamson, T. 1988. First-order logics for comparative similarity. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 29(4):457–481.
Yamada, T. 2007. Acts of commanding and changing obligations. In Proceedings of the 7th workshop on computational logic in multi-agent systems (CLIMA VII), eds. K. Inoue, K. Satoh, and F. Toni, 2006. Revised version appeared in LNAI 4371, 1–19. Springer: Heidelberg.
Yamada, T. 2008. Logical dynamics of some speech acts that affect obligations and preferences. Synthese 165(2):295–315.
Zarnic, B. 2003. Imperative change and obligation to do. In logic, law, morality: Thirteen essays in practical philosophy in Honour of Lennart Aqvist, eds. K. Segerberg and R. Sliwinski, 79–95. Uppsala philosophical studies 51. Uppsala: Uppsala University.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
Copyright information
© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.
About this chapter
Cite this chapter
Liu, F. (2011). Intermezzo: A Quantitative Approach. In: Reasoning about Preference Dynamics. Synthese Library, vol 354. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1344-4_6
Download citation
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1344-4_6
Published:
Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht
Print ISBN: 978-94-007-1343-7
Online ISBN: 978-94-007-1344-4
eBook Packages: Humanities, Social Sciences and LawPhilosophy and Religion (R0)