Abstract
In the preceding chapter, we have introduced a logical framework for static preference. Continuing on this platform, our main concern in this chapter is the dynamics of preference change. Our preferences are modified constantly through commands of moral authorities, suggestions from friends who give good advice, or just changes in our own evaluation of worlds and actions. Living in a society, our preference is also affected by what others like or dislike, as vividly described in the Chinese classic Record of Music 1:
Keywords
- Belief Revision
- Preference Change
- Dynamic Logic
- Public Announcement
- Default Rule
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.
Buying options



Notes
- 1.
The is the first work on music in Chinese history. It is believed that the book was written about two thousands year ago, but the precise time and author are still controversial.
- 2.
In addition to the arrows drawn, our betterness relations always have reflexive loops.
- 3.
Reference [105] analyzes newly defined betterness relations in a set-theoretic format.
- 4.
Just as with actions of public announcement in Chapter 2, the completeness theorem here does not give us an explicit valid principle for dealing with iterated modalities \(\langle\sharp \varphi\rangle\langle\sharp \psi\rangle \chi\). Indeed, there is no such principle, as the effect of two consecutive suggestions may be genuinely different from making just one suggestion. Consider a simpler principle \(\langle\sharp \varphi\rangle\langle\sharp \varphi\rangle \psi \leftrightarrow \langle\sharp \varphi\rangle\psi\), it holds for factual assertions φ. But it need not hold for non-factual φ which themselves refer to the ordering. After the first ♯φ action, we have changed the ordering, and the worlds where φ is now true need not be the same ones as those where φ was true before. Thus there is more structure to our dynamic logics than what we have brought to light so far.
- 5.
Reference [29] already noted how relativization and redefinition make up the standard notion of “relative interpretation” between theories in logic when objects are kept fixed – while product update relates to more complex reductions forming new objects as tuples of old objects.
- 6.
It is instructive to see the difference with \(\sharp \varphi(R)\) in the above PDL-style format.
- 7.
Conservative upgrade is a radical command to produce, not φ, but \(Best(\varphi)\).
- 8.
Such judgments occur in the literature on conditional obligation: see [96].
- 9.
We do not consider dynamic actions that directly transform the strict betterness relation, since these are less intuitive, while also presenting some technical difficulties.
- 10.
This “lexicographic” policy for belief revision was first suggested in [145].
References
van Benthem, J. 2007. Dynamic logic for belief revision. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logic 17:129–156.
van Benthem, J., J. van Eijck, and A. Frolova. 1993. Changing preferences. Technical Report, CS-93-10, Centre for Mathematics and Computer Science, Amsterdam.
van Benthem, J., and F. Liu. 2007. Dynamic logic of preference upgrade. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logic 17:157–182.
Grove, A. 1988. Two modelings for theory change. Journal of Philosophical Logic 17:157–170.
Hansson, B. 1969. An analysis of some deontic logics. Nous 3:373–398.
Hansson, S.O. 1995. Changes in preference. Theory and Decision 38:1–28.
Harel, D., D. Kozen, and J. Tiuryn. 2000. Dynamic logic. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Harrenstein, P. 2004. Logic in conflict. Logical explorations in strategic equilibrium. PhD thesis, Utrecht University.
Liu, F. 2008. Changing for the better: Preference dynamics and agent diversity. PhD thesis, ILLC, University of Amsterdam.
Nayak, A. 1994. Iterated belief change based on epistemic entrenchment. Erkentnis 41:353–390.
Prince, A., and P. Smolensky. 2004. Optimality theory: Constraint interaction in generative grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.
Rott, H. 2006. Shifting priorities: Simple representations for 27 iterated theory change operators. In Modality matters: Twenty-five essays in honour of Krister Segerberg, eds. H. Langerlund, S. Lindström, and R. Sliwinski, 359–384. Uppsala Philosophical Studies 53. Uppsala University: Uppsala.
Spohn, W. 1988. Ordinal conditional functions: A dynamic theory of epistemic states. In Causation in decision, belief change and statistics II, eds. W.L. Harper and B. Skyrms, 105–134. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
van der Torre, L. and Y. Tan. 1999. An update semantics for deontic reasoning. In Norms, logics and information systems, eds. P. McNamara and H. Prakken, 73–90. Amsterdam: IOS Press.
Veltman, F. 1996. Defaults in update semantics. Journal of Philosophical Logic 25:221–261.
Yamada, T. 2007. Acts of commanding and changing obligations. In Proceedings of the 7th workshop on computational logic in multi-agent systems (CLIMA VII), eds. K. Inoue, K. Satoh, and F. Toni, 2006. Revised version appeared in LNAI 4371, 1–19. Springer: Heidelberg.
Yamada, T. 2008. Logical dynamics of some speech acts that affect obligations and preferences. Synthese 165(2):295–315.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
Copyright information
© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.
About this chapter
Cite this chapter
Liu, F. (2011). Preference over Worlds: Dynamic Logic. In: Reasoning about Preference Dynamics. Synthese Library, vol 354. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1344-4_4
Download citation
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1344-4_4
Published:
Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht
Print ISBN: 978-94-007-1343-7
Online ISBN: 978-94-007-1344-4
eBook Packages: Humanities, Social Sciences and LawPhilosophy and Religion (R0)