Skip to main content

Part of the book series: The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science ((WONS,volume 75))

  • 1020 Accesses

Abstract

Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius (ca. 480–524) would have been most puzzled by what Shakespeare’s Lorenzo says. The reasons for his supposed perplexity lie in the background views on music that he appropriates from ancient Greek philosophy. Boethius’ compendium on music, De institutione musica (The Fundamentals of Music), along with similar texts on arithmetic, geometry and astronomy, formed the medieval quadrivium. It is surprising that the scholastic philosophers, who were often deeply concerned with logical consistency and order, were unperturbed by the inconsistencies running rampant throughout De institutione musica. On the one hand, the work’s first part is Pythagorean: music was inseparable from numbers, which governed the universe. Music exemplified the cosmic order. On the other hand, the work’s latter sections contain anti-Pythagorean sentiments; music is not necessarily anything that expresses universal orders. So, it is difficult to say precisely what Boethius thought about music. Further complicating this is the fact that, with respect to music, Boethius was not always a terribly original thinker. He often borrowed from a (now lost) treatise on music by Nicomachus and from the first book of Ptolemy’s Harmonics. Still, in the most original section of the book, the opening chapters, Boethius expresses a view of music that is relevant to the historical development of music and how thinkers addressed problems in the philosophy of music.

The man that hath no music in himself,

Nor is moved with concord of sweet sounds,

Is fit for treasons, stratagems, and spoils;

The motions of his spirit are dull as night,

And his affections dark as Erebus.

Let no such man be trusted. Mark the music.

The Merchant of Venice, Act V, Scene 1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This is an overstatement, but it is often made; the epic of Gilgamesh predates those of Homer.

  2. 2.

    For an overview of Milman’s work, see (Powell, 2004, Ch. 1), “The Philologist’s Homer.”

  3. 3.

    For an example of needless perplexity see (Smith, 2001, p. 7).

  4. 4.

    For more on Kant see (Kivy, 1997, pp. 15–18), and (Bicknell, 2002).

  5. 5.

    It is interesting to note that Paul Hindemith has the exact opposite view of music. “The reactions music evokes are not feelings, but they are the images, memories of feelings. Dreams, memories, musical reactions—all three are made of the same stuff.” Visual arts and poetry release direct emotions. Music is a trickster. “Paintings, poems, sculptures, works of architecture … do not—contrary to music—release images of feelings; instead they speak to the real, untransformed, and unmodified feelings.” (Hindemith, 1961, p.42)

  6. 6.

    Clearly some would argue that Theodor W. Adorno (1903–1969) would be a suitable candidate for such status.

  7. 7.

    (Goodman, 1976). The first edition appeared in 1968 and caused quite a stir in the academic world. A standard text for many kinds of arguments in aesthetics, somewhat dated now but still quite useful, is (Beardsley, 1981).

  8. 8.

    There are different kinds of formalist views of mathematics and often the formalist view is taken precisely to preserve some ontological view, such as Hilbert’s formalism as a means to defend the consistency of mathematics. For a general overview of this, see (Shapiro, 2000, Ch. 6).

  9. 9.

    It is interesting to note that Kivy rejects the form-content identity in music simply because the latter has no content. (See his “On the Unity of Form and Content” in (Kivy, 1997).) But again, this makes his notion of “enhanced formalism” very difficult to understand.

  10. 10.

    Would anyone call such an event a “piece of music?” Perhaps, and this raises the interesting, but difficult question of the ontology of music. I will return to this briefly at the end of this paper.

  11. 11.

    This, I suggest, is a large topic and merits much further exploration. However, that is a task for another time.

  12. 12.

    For an extended discussion of this question see (Robinson, 1994).

  13. 13.

    For an examination of the implicit metaphysics involved in making judgments concerning representations, see (Greaves, 2002).

  14. 14.

    For an extended critique of the resemblance theory of representation, see (Goodman, 1976, § 1), “Reality Remade.”

  15. 15.

    I am barely scratching the surface of all the problems connected to representation. For a general discussion see (Goodman, 1976).

  16. 16.

    This is another huge issue in the philosophy of science but one that I shall simply pass over here.

  17. 17.

    This is a subject of much dispute and involves many more issues than I can go into here. See (Davies, 2005).

Bibliography

  • Beardsley, M. C. (1981). Aesthetics: Problems in the Philosophy of Criticism. Hackett Publishing Co., Indianapolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bicknell, J. (2002). Can music convey semantic content? A Kantian approach. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 3:153–261.

    Google Scholar 

  • Critchley, M. (1977). Musicological epilepsy. In Critchley, M. and Henson, R. A., editors, Music and the Brain. Heineman Medical Books, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, S. (2005). The ontology of musical works and the authenticity of their performances. In Themes in the Philosophy of Music, pages 1–26. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1976). Languages of Art: An Approach to a Theory of Symbols. Hackett Publishing Co., Indianapolis, IN, Second Edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greaves, M. (2002). The Philosophical Status of Diagrams. CSLI Publications, Standford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grout, D. J. and Palisca, C. V., editors (1963). A History of Western Music. W.W. Norton, New York, NY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanslick, E. (1963). Music Criticism, 1846–99. Penguin Books, Harmondsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardy, G. H. (1969). A Mathematician’s Apology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. (1991). On the infinite. In Benacerraf, P. and Putnam, H., editors, Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, second edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hindemith, P. (1961). A Composer’s World. Anchor Books, New York, NY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kivy, P. (1990). Music Alone: Philosophical Reflections on Purely Musical Experience. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kivy, P. (1993). The Fine Art of Repetition: Essays in the Philosophy of Music. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kivy, P. (1997). Philosophies of Art: An Essay in Differences. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristeller, P. O. (1992). The modern system of the arts. In Kivy, P., editor, Essays on the History of Aesthetics. University of Rochester Press, Rochester, NY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machlis, J. (1970). The Enjoyment of Music. W.W. Norton & Company, New York, NY, 3rd edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menuhin, Y. (1972). Theme and Variations. Stein and Day, New York, NY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Powell, B. B. (2004). Homer. Blackwell Publishing, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1983). Models and reality. In Realism and Reason: Philosophical Papers, Volume 3, pages 1–26. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. Columbia University Press, New York, NY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, J. (1994). Music as a representational art. In Anderson, P., editor, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Music. Pennsylvania State Press, University Park.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sacks, O. (1981). Awakenings. Pan Books, London, revised edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, A. (1966). The World as Will and Representation, volume 1. Dover Books, New York, NY. transl. E. F. Payne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (2000). Thinking About Mathematics. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, N. D. (2001). Some thoughts about the origins of Greek ethics. The Journal of Ethics, 5:3–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1961). Tractatus-Logico-Philosophicus. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London. transl. David F. Pears and Brian F. McGuinness.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yewdale, M. S. (1928). The metaphysical foundations of pure music. The Musical Quarterly, 14(3):397–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Richard Feist .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Feist, R. (2011). Musing on Music. In: DeVidi, D., Hallett, M., Clarke, P. (eds) Logic, Mathematics, Philosophy, Vintage Enthusiasms. The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, vol 75. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-0214-1_25

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics