Advertisement

Wittgenstein, Kuhn and the Turn Towards Science Studies

  • Finn Collin
Chapter
Part of the Synthese Library book series (SYLI, volume 348)

Abstract

The version of philosophical naturalism that Science Studies adopted as its foundation was formulated by Ludwig Wittgenstein. Like Quine’s naturalism, Wittgenstein’s version sprang from disaffection with Carnap’s philosophy of language. But while Quine’s model of language as a network of inferential connections could immediately be transformed into a picture of scientific knowledge, there is no Wittgensteinian theory of science. However, one can be extrapolated from various parts of his work. What results is a picture of science showing a striking similarity to Kuhn’s celebrated paradigm model. And indeed, both Wittgenstein’s and Kuhn’s thinking constitute a significant part of the theoretical foundations of Science Studies. However, Science Studies aim at transcending the largely historical perspective of Kuhn, and replace it with a strictly sociological approach. Another and highly significant difference between Wittgenstein and Kuhn on one side and Science Studies on the other lies in STS’s critical attitude towards science and its status in society. I this, they articulate misgivings about science widespread in Western societies after World War II. There is an interesting parallel to the Frankfurt School on this point. The latter wanted to critique science from a purely philosophical perspective, however, whereas Science Studies adopted a naturalistic approach, using social science to debunk natural science.

Keywords

Science Policy Scientific Revolution Language Game Rational Reconstruction Frankfurt School 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Carnap, Rudolf. 1937. Logical syntax of language. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  2. Carnap, Rudolf. 1950. Logical foundations of probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  3. Carnap, Rudolf. 1952. The continuum of inductive methods. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  4. Feyerabend, Paul K. 1970. Consolations for the specialist. In Lakatos and Musgrave, 1970, 197–230.Google Scholar
  5. Habermas, Jürgen. 1971. Knowledge and human interests. Boston: Beacon Press. Translated from Erkenntnis und Interesse, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a. M., 1968.Google Scholar
  6. Hanson, Norwood Russell. 1958. Patterns of discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Kripke, Saul. 1982. Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Kuhn, Thomas S. 1962/1970. The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  9. Marcuse, Herbert. 1964. One-dimensional man. Boston: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
  10. Merton, Robert K. 1938. Science, technology and society in seventeenth century England. Osiris 4: 360–632.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Quine, Willard V.O. 1969a. Ontological relativity. In Ontological relativity and other essays: 26–68. New York and London: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Snow, C.P. 1959. The two cultures and the scientific revolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Toulmin, Stephen E. 1953. The philosophy of science. London: Hutchinson University Library.Google Scholar
  14. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1953. Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  15. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1969. On certainty. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  16. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1967a. Remarks on the foundations of mathematics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Dept of Media, Cognition and CommunicationUniversity of CopenhagenCopenhagenDenmark

Personalised recommendations