Advertisement

Quasi-truth and Quantum Mechanics

  • Newton C.A. da Costa
  • Otávio Bueno
Chapter
Part of the Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science book series (BSPS, volume 290)

Abstract

Since its early formulation, non-relativistic quantum mechanics (QM) has been the source of sustained controversy about its foundation. Despite its impressive empirical success, several foundational issues have not been settled by the theory: What exactly happens with the observables when a quantum system is not being measured? And what exactly happens during measurement? What is the nature of quantum particles? In particular, are they individuals or not? And can identity be applied to these particles? Not surprisingly, a variety of interpretations of QM have been developed in the attempt to address these and other foundational questions. Perhaps also not surprisingly, so far there has been no agreement as to which of these interpretations (if any) should be preferred.

Keywords

Quantum Mechanic Partial Structure Partial Relation Empirical Adequacy Copenhagen Interpretation 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Albert, D., Loewer, B. (1988). Interpreting the many worlds interpretation. Synthese, 77: 195–213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Barrett, J. (1999). The quantum mechanics of minds and worlds. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  3. Bohr, N. (1987/1998). The philosophical writings of Niels Bohr, vol. 4. Woodbridge: Ox Bow Press.Google Scholar
  4. Bueno, O. (1997). Empirical adequacy: a partial structures approach. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 28: 585–610.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. da Costa, N. C. A., French, S. (2003). Science and partial truth. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. De Witt, B. S. M. (1970). Quantum mechanics and reality. Physics Today, 23(9): 30–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Everett, H. (1957). Relative state formulation of quantum mechanics. Review of Modern Physics, 29: 454–462.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Heisenberg, W. (1955) The development of the interpretation of the quantum theory. In: Pauli, W., (ed.), Niels Bohr and the development of physics, vol. 35. London: Pergamon, pp. 12–29.Google Scholar
  9. Howard, D. (2004). Who invented the “Copenhagen interpretation”? A study in mythology. Philosophy of Science, 71: 669–682.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Mikenberg, I., da Costa, N. C. A., Chuaqui, R. (1986). Pragmatic truth and approximation to truth. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 51: 201–221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Vaidman, L. (1998). On schizophrenic experiences of the neutron or why we should believe in the many-worlds interpretation of quantum theory. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 12: 245–261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. van Fraassen, B. C. (1991). Quantum mechanics: an empiricist view. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  14. von Neumann, J. (1932). Mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics (English translation by R.T. Beyer, 1955). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyFederal University of Santa CatarinaFlorianópolisBrazil
  2. 2.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of MiamiCoral GablesUSA

Personalised recommendations