Instrumental or Immersed Experience: Pleasure, Pain and Object Perception in Locke

  • Lisa Shapiro
Part of the Studies in History and Philosophy of Science book series (AUST, volume 25)

Abstract

This paper aims to draw out two distinct strands in Locke’s account of our simple ideas of experience: an instrumental and an immersed model of experience. The place of pleasure and pain in sensation is key to the distinction between these two models. After showing this equivocation in Locke’s account, I consider its implications for his account of object perception, or our ideas of particular substances, and suggest that considering these issues in Locke might afford insight into contemporary discussions of the Binding Problem. I conclude by showing how Berkeley and Condillac resolve this equivocation in Locke and considering why Locke himself might have failed to do so.

References

  1. Anstey, Peter R., and Stephen A. Harris. 2006. Locke and Botany. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37(2) (June): 151–171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Aquinas, Thomas. 2002. The Treatise of Human Nature: Summa Theologiae 1a75–89. Ed. and trans. Robert Pasnau. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  3. Berkeley, George. 1713/1979. Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous. Ed. R.M. Adams. Indianapolis: Hackett. Cited internally as Dialogues, followed by edition page number.Google Scholar
  4. Berkeley, George. 1784/1910. A New Theory of Vision and Other Writings. Ed. Lindsay, A.D. London: Everyman’s Library. Cited internally as NTV followed by paragraph number.Google Scholar
  5. Bermùdez, J.L. 2007. The Object Properties Model of Object Perception: between the Binding Model and the Theoretical Model. Journal of Consciousness Studies 14(9–10): 43–65.Google Scholar
  6. Condillac, Étienne Bonnot de. 1754/1984. Traité des Sensations, Traité des Animaux. Paris: Fayard. Cited internally by TS, followed by Part, Chapter, Paragraph.Google Scholar
  7. Condillac, Étienne Bonnot de. 1903. Treatise on Sensations. Trans. Geraldine Carr. Los Angeles: USC Press.Google Scholar
  8. Descartes, René. 1985–1991. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, Vol I and II. Eds. and trans. Cottingham, Stoothof and Murdoch, and Vol III. Eds. and trans. Cottingham, Stoothof, Murdoch and Kenny. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Descartes, René. 1996/1908. Œuvres de Descartes. Eds. Charles Adam and Paul Tannery. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
  10. Downing, Lisa. 1997. Locke’s Newtonianism and Lockean Newtonianism. Perspectives on Science 5(3) (Fall): 285–310.Google Scholar
  11. Downing, Lisa. 1998. The Status of Mechanism in Locke’s Essay. Philosophical Review 107(3) (July): 381–414, http://www.csa.com (accessed July 22, 2009).
  12. James, William. 1950/1918. Principles of Psychology. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
  13. Jones, Jan-erik. 2007. Locke vs Boyle: The real essence of corpuscular species. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 15(4) (November): 659–684, http://www.csa.com (accessed July 22, 2009).
  14. Keating, Laura. 2002. Linking mechanism and subjectivity in Locke’s Essay. Locke Studies: An Annual Journal of Locke Research 2: 53–79.Google Scholar
  15. Locke, John. 1975. Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Ed. P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon. Cited internally as ECHU, followed by Book, Chapter, Paragraph.Google Scholar
  16. Meynell, Guy. 2003. Locke’s Corpuscularianism and Boyle’s Corpuscular Philosophy. Locke Studies: An Annual Journal of Locke Research 3: 133–145.Google Scholar
  17. Milton, J. R. 2001. Locke, Medicine and the Mechanical Philosophy. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 9(2) (June): 221–243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. O’Regan, J. K., Noë, A. 2001. A Sensorimotor Account of Vision and Visual Consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24: 939–1031.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Plate, J. 2007. An Analysis of the Binding Problem. Philosophical Psychology 20(6): 773–792.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Pylyshyn, Z. W. 2007. Things and Places: How the Mind Connects with the World. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  21. Sanchez-Gonzalez, Miguel A. 1990. Medicine in John Locke’s Philosophy. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy (December): 675–695.Google Scholar
  22. Simmons, Alison. 1999. Are Cartesian Sensations Representational? Noûs 33(3): 347–369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Spinoza, Baruch. 1985. The Collected Works of Spinoza, Vol.1. Ed. and trans. E. Curley. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Stein, Howard. 1990. On Locke, ‘the Great Huygenius, and the incomparable Mr. Newton’. Philosophical Perspectives on Newtonian Science. Eds. Philip Bricker and RIG Hughes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  25. Walmsley, Jonathan. 2008. Sydenham and the Development of Locke’s Natural Philosophy. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 16(1) (February): 65–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Wilson, Catherine. 1995. The Invisible World: Early Modern Philosophy and the Invention of the Microscope. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010

Authors and Affiliations

  • Lisa Shapiro
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophySimon Fraser UniversityBurnabyCanada

Personalised recommendations