Skip to main content

Beyond Cynicism and Critique: International Law and the Possibility of Change

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 562 Accesses

Part of the book series: Beiträge zum ausländischen öffentlichen Recht und Völkerrecht ((BEITRÄGE,volume 296))

Abstract

In this chapter, I seek to map and analyse potential negative consequences of cynicism and critique in international law scholarship. Clearly, there is a lot to be cynical and critical about and many reasons for wanting to change the world. But I argue that for real change both discursive practices can have the unintended effect of contributing to the legitimation of the status quo. Using examples from international criminal law, I show how cynicism and critique are not productive as such. I also demonstrate, among other consequences, that the more one uncovers the hidden mechanisms and structures of power in international law, the fewer alternatives cynics as well as critics are able to identify, leading them to believe that reality—while lamentable—is still the best of all possible worlds. To overcome this fatalism, I call for imagining new strategies for change that go beyond existing categories of law and legal institutions. As an illustration, I present an alternative programme for international criminal law that focuses on removing the structural root causes of violence rather than mitigating only individual symptoms.

The author would like to thank Janne Nijman, Dana Burchardt and Linus Mührel for very valuable comments on earlier drafts of this chapter and Oleksandra Novikova for excellent research assistance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Chomsky (2017), p. 196.

  2. 2.

    Kennedy (2016), pp. 31–32.

  3. 3.

    Schwöbel (2014), p. 8, already raised this issue in relation to critique of international criminal law asking ‘[i]n how far does an engaged critique (a dialectic between practice and theory) strengthen precisely those structures which it aims to unsettle?’

  4. 4.

    Baloyra (1979), p. 994.

  5. 5.

    Sloterdijk (1987), pp. 5–6. For a discussion of the different concepts of cynicism, see Björnstjern Baade et al., ‘How (Not) to Be Cynical’, in this volume; and Hengameh Saberi, ‘Cynicism as a Modus of Political Agency: Can It Speak to International Law’, in this volume.

  6. 6.

    This is very well captured in Brecht’s Threepenny Opera: ‘Wir wären gut, anstatt so roh, / Doch die Verhältnisse, sie sind nicht so!’ (‘We’d like to be good instead of so mean, but the conditions just won’t allow it’.).

  7. 7.

    Christine Schwöbel uses a distinction within critics: ‘effectiveness critique’ on the one hand, dealing merely with the question of how to make the existing institutions more effective and ‘assumptions critique’ on the other hand, that seeks to question the underlying assumptions of the usefulness of institutions in the first place, see Schwöbel (2014), pp. 3–4. The arguments advanced here apply to both forms of critique.

  8. 8.

    MacAskill (2017), p. 2; Singer (2015), pp. 4–5.

  9. 9.

    I am here mostly influenced by Judith Shklar’s view on legalism as ideology, see Shklar (1986). See also Posner (2009), Hurd (2017). On the limitation of knowing due to differing social positions that generate variable constructions of reality and afford different perspectives on the world, see generally Alcoff (2007).

  10. 10.

    Rudolph (2017), pp. 89–112.

  11. 11.

    Id.

  12. 12.

    Alcoff (2007).

  13. 13.

    https://www.gov.uk/government/speeches/uk-statement-to-icc-assembly-of-states-parties-17th-session. Accessed 30 April 2020.

  14. 14.

    See for an overview of the International Criminal Court’s problems, Guilfoyle (2019). On the problem of double standards at the International Criminal Court, see Lentner (2020).

  15. 15.

    Chimni (2004), pp. 13–14.

  16. 16.

    Doudou Thiam (Special Rapporteur), Third Report on the Draft Code of Offences against the Peace and Security of Mankind, UN Doc A/CN.4/387 (8 Apr 1985), paras. 157–162.

  17. 17.

    On the ICC’s actions in Africa, see Branch (2017).

  18. 18.

    https://www.un.org/africarenewal/magazine/may-july-2017/icc-beyond-threats-withdrawal. Accessed 30 April 2020.

  19. 19.

    See on the status of the preliminary examinations and investigations, https://www.icc-cpi.int/pages/pe.aspx. Accessed 30 April 2020.

  20. 20.

    See generally on the ICC’s African dilemmas, Branch (2017).

  21. 21.

    Kennedy and Tennant (1994), p. 427 (comments made by Martti Koskenniemi).

  22. 22.

    Jodoin and Lofts (2014), pp. 333–334.

  23. 23.

    Kennedy (2016), p. 32.

  24. 24.

    Id., p. 112.

  25. 25.

    Moyn (2018).

  26. 26.

    Kennedy (2002), pp. 119–120.

  27. 27.

    These questions have, for example, motivated an entire movement of so-called effective altruists who seek to maximise their contribution to make other peoples’ lives better, see Singer (2015).

  28. 28.

    Cooper (2014), p. 217.

  29. 29.

    On the ICC’s progress narrative, see Armenian (2016).

  30. 30.

    See Kennedy (2000), pp. 105–106. For challenging the latter, see Lentner (2018), pp. 10–31. An example of this in foreign policy is the unfulfilled promise of change during the Obama administration. Instead of transformational change of US foreign policy, Obama merely engaged in ‘modest reform under primacy and market liberalism, instead of the transformational change he promised, while rhapsodising about the arc of the moral universe. This … preclud[es] any reassessment of the fundamentals, which are fixed and sound, presupposing the status quo and history’s direction’, Porter (2020).

  31. 31.

    See also Schwöbel (2014), p. 12.

  32. 32.

    Challenging this narrative, see Lentner (2020).

  33. 33.

    Plato (1968), 339a, 16; Bass (2000), p. 9.

  34. 34.

    Kennedy (2016), p. 259.

  35. 35.

    Sypnowich (2014).

  36. 36.

    Anghie (2006), Anghie (2004) and Bowden (2005).

  37. 37.

    Snyder (2018), p. 7.

  38. 38.

    The idea that ‘humanity is moving in the direction of better and more perfect civilization, and that this progression can be witnessed through study of the history of civilization’ itself reaches back to enlightenment thinking, where it replaced religious interpretations of history, see Little (2017).

  39. 39.

    I do not seek to impose this as a requirement of critique. On this point I agree with political theorist Raymond Geuss when he writes about ‘the effort to impose the requirement of “positivity” or “constructiveness” on potential critics: you can’t criticise the police system, the system of labour law, the organisation of the health services, etc., unless you have a completely elaborated, positive alternative to propose. … to accept it is to allow the existing social formation to dictate the terms on which it can be criticised, and to allow it to impose a theoretically unwarranted burden of positive proof on any potential critic’. Geuss (2008), pp. 95–96. However, as a general attitude towards knowledge production, I do advocate investing resources into finding alternatives as part of any critical endeavour.

  40. 40.

    Decision Pursuant to Article 15 of the Rome Statute on the Authorisation of an Investigation into the Situation in the Islamic Republic of Afghanistan, Pre-Trial Chamber II, ICC-02/17-33 (12 Apr 2019).

  41. 41.

    Schlag (1989/90).

  42. 42.

    Ginsburg and Stephanopoulos (2017), p. 147.

  43. 43.

    d’Aspremont (2020) and Schlag (1989/90).

  44. 44.

    Kennedy (2002), p. 108.

  45. 45.

    See e.g. Nowak (2015).

  46. 46.

    Kennedy (2002), p. 108.

  47. 47.

    Rosen (2006), pp. 4–5.

  48. 48.

    MacCormick (1995), p. 470; Veitch (2007), p. 77. Developing this idea further for the role of international law in international relations, see Hurd (2017).

  49. 49.

    Kahn (1999), pp. 138–139. In a similar vein, see d’Aspremont (2020), p. 10.

  50. 50.

    Alcoff (2007), p. 41 See also Lentner (2019).

  51. 51.

    Hurd (2017), pp. 129–138.

  52. 52.

    Id., p. 129.

  53. 53.

    Id., pp. 132–135.

  54. 54.

    Kennedy (2012), p. 24.

  55. 55.

    Id., p. 24.

  56. 56.

    Id.

  57. 57.

    Id., p. 20.

  58. 58.

    Id., p. 26.

  59. 59.

    Friedman (2016), pp. 97–138.

  60. 60.

    Generally, on prerequisites and factors for deterrence (that when applied to international criminal law does not easily suggest effective deterrence through international criminal law as it stands today) Friedman (2016), pp. 97–138. Doubting deterrent effects of international criminal law, specifically see Lentner (2018), p. 31; Hopgood (2013), p. 14; Tallgren (2002), p. 590; Vinjamuri (2010), pp. 205–206; Mohamed (2015), p. 1639. On the other hand, there are empirical studies that do suggest some effect on prevention of crimes, for an overview of existing studies, see Ford (2020). However, it is important to note the limitations of these empirical studies, as it is difficult to control for all variables that might better explain the phenomenon of reduced atrocity crimes being committed (so-called confounding variables).

  61. 61.

    Nouwen (2013).

  62. 62.

    Trying to fill that gap with a legal duty of states to prevent genocide, see Heieck (2018).

  63. 63.

    Reisman (2007–2009), p. 60.

  64. 64.

    Mohamed (2015), p. 1685. See also Bass (2000).

  65. 65.

    See for the general (polemic) critique of an unwarranted belief in the effectiveness of international courts based merely on their existence in Reisman (1993), p. 414 (‘This is all very discouraging for the incurable judicial romantics who look to courts as a type of deus ex machina, ready to descend, upon the mere utterance of some juridical incantations, and, thanks to mysterious powers inherent in the law, to bring order and justice to the most untidy, even violent political situations. Many judicial romantics subconsciously transpose some of the powerful emotive affects of the symbol “court” in municipal systems, where they have been significant struts of public order, to radically different environments. This can be disappointing and even dangerous. A court, by itself, is only a college of people. Its powers in any setting derive from a political process, of which it is a part, and which enfranchises it.’).

  66. 66.

    Knox (2009), pp. 430–431.

  67. 67.

    Linarelli et al. (2018), pp. 20–21.

  68. 68.

    Koskenniemi (2019), p. 7.

  69. 69.

    Schlag (1989/90) and d’Aspremont (2020).

  70. 70.

    Kennedy (2000), p. 104.

  71. 71.

    See Stiglitz (2001), pp. xv–xvi.

  72. 72.

    Linarelli et al. (2018), p. 18.

  73. 73.

    On the importance of individual prosecutions and actual enforcement of law see generally the empirical work on these questions, Friedman (2016). Punishment is a whole other issue, see Fassin (2018).

  74. 74.

    With respect to human rights law, see Kennedy (2002), p. 123.

  75. 75.

    Cf. Kennedy (2012), p. 20.

  76. 76.

    See e.g. the Report of the UN Secretary-General, Implementing the Responsibility to Protect: Accountability for Prevention, UN Doc A/71/1016-S/2017/556 (10 Aug 2017), paras. 13, 20, 24.

  77. 77.

    Lee (2016), p. 113.

  78. 78.

    Id., p. 113.

  79. 79.

    Id., p. 110; Farmer (2004), p. 307. See also Galtung (1969), pp. 167–191. Galtung thought that structural violence could be avoided when people become conscious of the imposition of limitations by social structures. For similar arguments on the connection between structural violence and poverty, see Pogge (2008).

  80. 80.

    Lee (2016), p. 110.

  81. 81.

    Id., p. 110.

  82. 82.

    Mohamed (2015), p. 1685.

  83. 83.

    Kennedy (2002), p. 118.

  84. 84.

    McLoughlin (2014), p. 413.

  85. 85.

    Id., pp. 409–413.

  86. 86.

    Uvin (2010), pp. 170–175.

  87. 87.

    McLoughlin (2014), pp. 422–423.

  88. 88.

    McLoughlin (2014), pp. 433–439.

  89. 89.

    McLoughlin (2014), pp. 424–425.

  90. 90.

    McLoughlin (2015), p. 29.

  91. 91.

    Haraway (1988).

  92. 92.

    Manne (2018), p. 32. See further Haslanger (2012), pp. 11, 411–418.

  93. 93.

    Karl Marx, Theses on Feuerbach.

References

  • Alcoff, L. M. (2007). Epistemology of ignorance: Three types. In S. Shannon & T. Nancy (Eds.), Race and epistemologies of ignorance: Three types (pp. 39–57). New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anghie, A. (2004). Imperialism, sovereignty and the making of international law. Cambridge: CUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anghie, A. (2006). The evolution of international law: Colonial and postcolonial realities. Third World Quarterly, 27(5), 739–753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Armenian, A. V. (2016). Selectivity in international criminal law: An assessment of the ‘Progress narrative’. International Criminal Law Review, 16(4), 642–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baloyra, E. A. (1979). Criticism, cynicism, and political evaluation: A Venezuelan example. American Political Science Review, 73(4), 987–1002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bass, G. J. (2000). Stay the hand of vengeance. The politics of war crimes tribunals. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bowden, B. (2005). The colonial origins of international law. European expansion and the classical standard of civilization. Journal of the History of International Law, 7(1), 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Branch, A. (2017). Dominic Ongwen on trial: The ICC’s African dilemmas. International Journal of Transitional Justice, 11(1), 30–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chimni, B. S. (2004). International institutions today: An imperial global state in the making. European Journal of International Law, 15(1), 1–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2017). Optimism over Despair. On capitalism, empire, and social change. Chicago: Haymarket Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, D. (2014). Everyday utopias the conceptual life of promising spaces. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • d’Aspremont, J. (2020). International legal methods: Working for a tragic and cynical routine. In R. Deplano & N. Tsagourias (Eds.), Handbook on research methods in international law. Cheltenham: Elgar. (in press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Farmer, P. (2004). An anthropology of structural violence. Current Anthropology, 45(3), 305–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fassin, D. (2018). Der Wille zum Strafen. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ford, S. (2020). Can the International Criminal Court Succeed? An analysis of the empirical evidence related to violence prevention. Loyola of Los Angeles International and Comparative Law Review, forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, L. M. (2016). Impact. How law affects behavior. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galtung, J. (1969). Violence, peace, and peace research. Journal of Peace Research, 6(3), 167–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginsburg, T., & Stephanopoulos, N. (2017). The concepts of law. University of Chicago Law Review, 84(1), 147–175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geuss, R. (2008). Philosophy and real politics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Guilfoyle, D. (2019). This Is Not Fine: The International Criminal Court in Trouble. EJIL: Talk! Retrieved 30 April 2020, from http://www.ejiltalk.org/part-i-this-is-not-fine-the-international-criminal-court-in-trouble/

  • Haraway, D. (1988). Situated knowledges: The science question in feminism and the privilege of partial perspective. Feminist Studies, 14(3), 575–599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. A. (2012). Resisting reality: Social construction and social critique. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heieck, J. (2018). A duty to prevent genocide. Due Diligence obligations among the P5. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hopgood, S. (2013). The endtimes of human rights. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurd, I. (2017). How to do things with international law. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jodoin, S., & Lofts, K. (2014). What’s critical about critical international law? In P. Singh & B. Mayer (Eds.), Critical international law (pp. 326–346). Oxford: OUP.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kahn, P. W. (1999). The cultural study of law. Reconstructing legal scholarship. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy D (2000) What is new thinking in international law? Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the American Society of International Law, 94, 104–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, D. (2002). The international human rights movement: Part of the problem? Harvard Human Rights Journal, 15, 99–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, D. (2012). The international human rights regime: Still part of the problem? In R. Dickinson, E. Katselli, C. Murray, & O. W. Pedersen (Eds.), Examining critical perspective on human rights (pp. 19–34). Cambridge: CUP.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, D. (2016). A world of struggle. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, D., & Tennant, C. (1994). New approaches to international law: A bibliography. Harvard International Law Journal, 35(2), 417–460.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knox, R. (2009). Marxism, international law, and political strategy. Leiden Journal of International Law, 22(3), 413–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koskenniemi, M. (2019). International law and the far right: Reflections on law and cynicism. The Hague: TMC Asser Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee, B. X. (2016). Causes and cures IX: Consequences of violence. Aggression and Violent Behavior, 30, 110–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lentner, G. (2018). The UN security council and the international criminal court. The referral mechanism in theory and practice. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lentner, G. (2019). Law, language, and power: English and the production of ignorance in international law. International Journal of Language & Law, 8, 50–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lentner, G. (2020). The lasting legacy of double standards: The international criminal court and the UN security council referral mechanism. International Criminal Law Review, 20(2), 251–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Linarelli, J., Salomon, M. E., & Sornarajah, M. (2018). The misery of international law. Confrontations with injustice in the global economy. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (2017). Philosophy of history. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 30 April 2020, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/history/

  • MacAskill, W. (2017). Effective altruism: Introduction. Essays in Philosophy, 18(1), 1–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. (1995). Argumentation and interpretation in law. Argumentation, 9(3), 467.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manne, K. (2018). Down Girl. The logic of misogyny. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLoughlin, S. (2014). Rethinking the structural prevention of mass atrocities. Global Responsibility to Protect, 6(4), 407–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLoughlin, S. (2015). Understanding mass atrocity prevention during periods of democratic transition. Politics and Governance, 3(3), 27–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mohamed, S. (2014/2015). Deviance, aspiration, and the stories we tell: Reconciling mass atrocity and the criminal law. Yale Law Journal, 124(5), 1628–1689.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moyn, S. (2018). Law Schools are bad for democracy. The Chronicle Review. Retrieved 30 April 2020, from https://www.chronicle.com/article/Law-Schools-Are-Bad-for/245334

  • Nouwen, S. M. H. (2013). Complementarity in the line of fire. The catalysing effect of the international criminal court in Uganda and Sudan. Cambridge: CUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nowak, M. (2015). Menschenrechte — Eine Antwort auf die wachsende ökonomische Ungleichheit. Vienna: Konturen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, T. (2008). World poverty and human rights. Cosmopolitan responsibilities and reforms (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter, P. (2020). Speaking Truth to Power. The Critic. Retrieved 30 April 2020, from https://thecritic.co.uk/issues/february-2020/speaking-truth-to-power/

  • Posner, E. A. (2009). The perils of global legalism. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reisman, W. M. (1993). The constitutional crisis in the United Nations. In R. J. Dupuy (Ed.), Le Développement du Rôle du Conseil de Sécurité. Peace-Keeping and Peace-Building. Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reisman, W. M. (2007–2009). Acting before Victims become Victims: Preventing and Arresting Mass Murder. Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law, 40(1–2), 57–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, L. (2006). Law as culture: An invitation. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rudolph, C. (2017). Power and principle. The politics of international criminal courts. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schlag, P. (1989/90). ‘Le hors de Texte, C’est Moi’: The politics of form and the domestication of deconstruction. Cardozo Law Review, 11(5–6), 1631–1674.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwöbel, C. E. J. (2014). Introduction. In C. E. J. Schwöbel (Ed.), Critical approaches to international criminal law. An introduction. New York: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shklar, J. N. (1986). Legalism: Law, morals, and political trials. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (2015). The most good you can do. How effective altruism is changing ideas about living ethically. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloterdijk, P. (1987). Critique of cynical reason. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, T. (2018). The road to unfreedom. Russia, Europe, America. New York: Tim Duggan Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiglitz, J. (2001). Foreword. In K. Polanyi (Ed.), The great transformation: The political and economic origins of our time (pp. xv–xvi). Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sypnowich, C. (2014). Law and ideology. In E. N. Z. Edward (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 30 April 2020, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/law-ideology/

  • Tallgren, I. (2002). The sensibility and sense of international criminal law. European Journal of International Law, 13(3), 561–595.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uvin, P. (2010). Structural causes, development co-operation and conflict prevention in Burundi and Rwanda. Conflict, Security & Development, 10(1), 161–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veitch, S. (2007). Law and irresponsibility. On the legitimation of human suffering. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vinjamuri, L. (2010). Deterrence, democracy, and the pursuit of international justice. Ethics & International Affairs, 24(2), 191–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer-Verlag GmbH, DE, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Lentner, G.M. (2021). Beyond Cynicism and Critique: International Law and the Possibility of Change. In: Baade, B., et al. Cynical International Law?. Beiträge zum ausländischen öffentlichen Recht und Völkerrecht, vol 296. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-62128-8_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-62128-8_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-662-62127-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-662-62128-8

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics