Advertisement

A Quantum Theory of Consciousness

  • Henry P. Stapp
Part of the The Frontiers Collection book series (FRONTCOLL)

Abstract

Classical physics has no natural place for consciousness. According to the classical precepts, the sole ingredients of the physical universe are particles and local fields, and every physical system is completely described by specifying the dispositions in space and time of these two kinds of localizable parts. Furthermore, the dispositions of these parts at early times determine, through certain “laws of motion”, their dispositions at all times. The system is logically complete in the sense that it does not logically require, for its description of nature, any things beyond the dispositions of the particles and local fields.

Keywords

Quantum Theory Classical Physic Conscious Experience Body Schema Conscious Thought 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 1.
    H. P. Stapp, The Copenhagen Interpretation, Am. J. Phys. 40, 1098 (1972) and chap. 3 of the present book.ADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. 2.
    H. P. Stapp, Quantum Nonlocality and the Description of Nature, in Philosophical Consequences of Quantum Theory, edited by J. Cushing and E. McMullin (Notre Dame University Press, 1989), pp. 154–174;Google Scholar
  3. 2a.
    H. P. Stapp, EPR and Bell’s Theorem: A Critical Review, Found. Phys. 21, 1 (1991);MathSciNetADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. 2b.
    H. P. Stapp, Noise-Induced Reduction of Wave Packets and Faster-than-Light Influence, Phys. Rev. A 46, 6860 (1992); (with D. Bedford), Bell’s Theorem in an Indeterministic Universe, submitted to Synthese. ADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. 3.
    W. Heisenberg, Physics and Philosophy (Harper and Row, New York, 1958), chap. III.Google Scholar
  6. 4.
    H. P. Stapp, Quantum Theory and Emergence of Patterns in the Universe, in Bell’s Theorem, Quantum Theory, and Conceptions of the Universe, edited by Menas Kafatos (Kluwer, Dordrecht, Boston, 1989).Google Scholar
  7. 5.
    J.I. Hubbard, Mechanism of Transmitter Release, Prog. Biophys. Mol. Biol. 21, 33 (1970).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. 6.
    L. Ingber, Statistical Mechanics of Neocortical Interactions. Dynamics of Synaptic Modification, Phys. Rev. A 28, 395–416 (1983);ADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. 6a.
    L. Ingber, Statistical Mechanics of Neocortical Interactions. Derivation of Short-Term-Memory Capacity, Phys. Rev. A 29, 3346–3358 (1984).ADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. 7.
    J. von Neumann, Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1955);zbMATHGoogle Scholar
  11. 7a.
    E. Wigner, Remarks on the Mind-Body Problem, in The Scientist Speculates, edited by I. J. Good (Heinemann, London, and Basic Books, New York, 1962).Google Scholar
  12. 8.
    H. P. Stapp, A Quantum Theory of the Mind-Brain Interface, Lawrence Berkeley Laboratory Report LBL-28574 Expanded, University of California, Berkeley, 1991, and chap. 6 of the present book.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2004

Authors and Affiliations

  • Henry P. Stapp
    • 1
  1. 1.Lawrence Berkeley LaboratoryBerkeleyUSA

Personalised recommendations