Skip to main content

Sources for the History of the Concept of Symbol from Leibniz to Cassirer

  • Chapter
Symbol and Physical Knowledge

Abstract

According to Ernst Cassirer, the problem and the concept of the symbolical function may be considered as the core of the philosophical inquiry (Cassirer, 1985, p. 1). To be sure, many philosophers of the 20th century agree with Cassirer’s point of view. As Alfred North Whitehead remarked, “symbolism” does not constitute an idle fantasy, but is immanent to human existence (Whitehead, 1958, p. 61–62). Nevertheless this “immanence” can be interpreted in different ways. The relationship of the symbols with reality, the role played by symbols in our mental activity, the various manners of “constructing the world” on the basis of human symbolisation, are all challenges to most of the philosophical disciplines.1 This is particulary true in the field of epistemology. Questions such as the meaning of symbols within scientific knowledge, their epistemological status, whether and to what extent they are constitutive conditions of experience, and eventually the possibility of considering the “symbolic form” of knowledge as an unavoidable semiotic function of the scientific grasping of reality are problems concerning not only the “archeology” of the philosophical tradition, but also and firstly the philosophical tasks as well as our contemporary debates.

“Ich getraue mir zu behaupten, daß die unauflöslichen Schwierigkeiten, und die wichtigen Streitigkeiten in den Wissenschaften aus Mangel an Einsicht in die Natur der symbolischen Erkenntnis entstanden sind, und daß also die Hebung jener Schwierigkeiten, die Beilegung jener Streitigkeiten bloß dadurch bewerkstelliget werden könne, wenn man die Gränzen der symbolischen Erkenntnis in Ansehnung ihres Gebrauchs festsetzte, ihre verschiedenen Arten bestimmte, und die Symbolik selbst (das Zeichensystem) diesem gemäß einrichtete.” (Maimom, 1963, p. 265.)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • D. Baird, R.I.G. Hughes, A. Nordmann (Eds.) (1998), Heinrich Hertz: Classical Physicist, Modern Philosopher, Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • F. Barone (1999), Logica formale e logica trascendentale, I, Da Leibniz a Kant (1957), Milano: Unicopli.

    Google Scholar 

  • F. Barone (2000), Logica formale e logica trascendentale, II, L’algebra della logica (1965), Milano: Unicopli.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Boole (1950), An Investigation of the Laws of Thought on which are founded the mathematical theories of Logic and Probabilities (1854), New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Boole (1951), The Mathematical Analysis of Logic. Being an Essay towards a Calculus of Deductive Reasoning (1847), Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Boole (1997), Selected Manuscripts on Logic and its Philosophy, edited by I. Grattan-Guinness and G. Bornet, Basel-Boston-Berlin: Birkhäuser Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • T. Borsche (1981), Sprachansichten. Der Begriff der menschlichen Rede in der Sprachphilosophie Wilhelm von Humboldts, Stuttgart: Klet-Cotta.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Buzzetti and M. Ferriani (Eds.) (1987), Speculative Grammar, Universal Grammar and Philosophical Analysis of Language, Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Capozzi (1987), Kant on Logic, Language and Thought, in: M. Buzzetti and M. Ferriani (Eds.), pp. 97–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Carnap (1979), Der logische Aufbau der Welt (1928), Frankfurt am Main/Berlin/Wien: Ullstein.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Cassirer (1902), Leibniz’ System in seinen wissenschaftlichen Grundlagen, Marburg: Elwert.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Cassirer (1953a), Substance and Function and Einstein’s Theory of Relativity (1910–1923), transl. by W. Curtis Swabey and M. Collins, New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Cassirer (1953b), The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, vol. I: Language (1923), New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Cassirer (1957), The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, vol. III: The Phenomenology of Knowledge (1929), New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Cassirer (1983), Wesen und Wirkung des Symbolbegriffs, Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Cassirer (1985), Symbol, Technik, Sprache. Aufsätze aus den Jahren 1927–1933, edited by E.W. Orth and J.M. Krois, Hamburg: Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Cassirer (1991), Das Erkenntnisproblem in der Philosophie und Wissenschaft der neueren Zeit, vol. IV: Von Hegels Tod bis zur Gegenwart (1957), Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Cassirer (1995), Das Erkenntnisproblem in der Philosophie und Wissenschaft der neueren Zeit, second revised edition, (1910–1911), 2 vols., Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • H.-J. Dahms (Ed.) (1985), Philosophie, Wissenschaft, Aufklärung. Beiträge zur Geschichte und Wirkung des Wiener Kreises, Berlin-New York: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • T. De Mauro and L. Formigari (Eds.) (1989), Leibniz, Humboldt and the Origins of Comparative Linguistic, Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • H.G. Dosch (1997), The Concept of Sign and Symbol in the Work of Hermann Helmholtz and Heinrich Hertz, Etudes de Lettres 1–2: 74–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Duhem (1981), La théorie physique. Son object et sa structure (1906), Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Ferrari (1995), Ernst Cassirer und Pierre Duhem, in: E. Rudolph and B.O. Küppers (Eds.) (1995), pp. 177–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Ferrari (1996), Ernst Cassirer. Dalla scuola di Marburgo alla filosofia della cultura, Firenze: Olschki.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Ferrari (1997), Introduzione a Il neocriticismo, Roma- Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Fölsing (1997), Heinrich Hertz. Eine Biographie, Hamburg: Hoffmann und Campe.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Frege (1879), Begriffschrift, eine der aritmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens, Halle: Nebert.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Frege (1979), Posthumous Writings, edited by H. Hermes, F. Kambartel, F. Kaulbach, Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Frege (1980), Funktion, Begriff, Bedeutung, edited by G. Patzig, Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Friedman (1997), Helmholtz’s Zeichentheorie and Schlick’s Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre: Early Logical Empiricism and Its Nineteenth-Century Background, in: Philosophical Topics XXV 19–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • E. Garroni (1998), Estetica ed epistemologia. Riflessioni sulla “Critica del Giudizio”, Milano: Edizioni Unicopli.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Ghio (1979), Il concetto di espressione in Leibniz e nella tradizione platonicocristiana, Torino: Edizioni di “Filosofia” .

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Haller (1993), Neopositivismus. Eine historische Einführung in die Philosophie des Wiener Kreises, Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Heidelberger, From Helmholtz’s Philosophy of Science to Hertz’s Picture-Theory, in: D. Baird-R.I.G., Hughes-A. Nordmann (Eds.) (1998), pp. 9–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Heinekamp (1988), Natürliche Sprache und allgemeine Charakteristik bei Leibniz (1972/1975), in: Leibniz Logik und Metaphysik, A. Heinekamp-F. Schuppe (Eds.), (Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, Darmstadt) pp. 349–386.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Heinekamp and F. Schuppe (Eds.) (1988), Leibniz’ Logik und Metaphysik, Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Hertz (1963), Die Prinzipien der Mechanik in neuem Zusammenhange dargestellt (1894), Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Janik (1994/1995), How Did Hertz influence Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Development? Grazer Philosophische Studien 49: 19–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • I. Kant (1902ff.), Kant’s Gesammelte Schriften. Akademie Ausgabe, vols. I–XII, Berlin: Reimer.

    Google Scholar 

  • I. Kant (1963), Critique of Pure Reason, transl. by N. Kemp Smith, London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • I. Kant (1973), The Critique of Judgement, transl. by J. Creed Meredith, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • I. Kant (1981), Schriften zur Metaphysik und Logik, edited by. W. Weischedel, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp (Werkausgabe, vol. VI) .

    Google Scholar 

  • I. Kant (1992), Theoretical Philosophy 1755–1770, transl. and edited by D. Walford in collaboration with R. Meerbote, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • I. Kant (1996), Practical Philosophy, transl. by M.J. Gregor, general introduction by A. Wood, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • E.-W. Kluge (1977), Frege, Leibniz et alii, Studia Leibnitiana IX: 266–274.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • E.-W. Kluge (1980), The Metaphysics of Gottlob Frege. An Essay in Ontological reconstruction, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • K.Ch. Köhnke (1986), Entstehung und Aufstieg des Neukantianismus. Die deutsche Universitätsphilosophie zwischen Idealismus und Positivismus, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • S. Krämer (1992), Symbolische Erkenntnis bei Leibniz Z. Philos. Forsch. XLVI: 224–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • M.A. Kulstad (1976), Leibniz Conception of Expression, Stud. Leibnitiana IX: 56–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Lamacchia (1990), Percorsi kantiani, Bari: Levante Editori.

    Google Scholar 

  • J.H. Lambert (1965/1968), Philosophischen Schriften, ed. by H.-W. Arndt, 10 vols., Hildesheim: Olms.

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz (1875–1890), Philosophische Schriften, edited by C.I. Gerhardt, 7 vols., Berlin: Weidemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz (1951), Selections, edited by Ph.P. Wiener, New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz (1966), Hauptschriften zur Grundlegung der Philosophie (1904/1906), edited by E. Cassirer, 2 vols., Hamburg: Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • S. Maimon (1963), Versuch über die transzendentale Philosophie mit einem Anhang über symbolische Erkenntnis und Anmerkungen (1790), Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • U. Majer (1985), Hertz, Wittgenstein und der Wiener Kreis, in: H.-J. Dahms (editor) (1985), pp. 40–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • U. Majer (1998), Heinrich Hertz’s Picture-Conception of Theories: Its Elaboration by Hilbert, Weyl, and Ramsey, in: D. Baird-R.I.G. Hughes-A. Nordmann (Eds.) (1998), pp. 225–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Mugnai (1976), Astrazione e réaltà. Saggio su Leibniz, Milan: Feltrinelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Patzig (1969), Leibniz, Frege und die sogennante “lingua characterica universalis”, in: Studia Leibnitiana Supplementa, vol. III, Wiesbaden: Steiner Verlag, pp. 103–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • V. Peckhaus (1997), Logik, Mathesis universalis und allgemeine Wissenschaft. Leibniz und die Wiederentdeckung der formalen Logik im 19. Jahrhundert, Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • C.S. Peirce (1934), Collected Papers, edited by Ch. Hartshorne and P. Weiss, vol. V: Pragmatism and Pragmaticism, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • C.S. Peirce (1982), Writings. A Chronological edition, edited by M.H. Fish, vol. I: 1857–1866, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • C.S. Peirce (1984), Writings. A Chronological edition, edited by M.H. Fish, vol. II: 1867–1871, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • F. Piro (1990), Varietas identitate compensata. Studio sulla formazione della metafisica di Leibniz, Napoli: Bibliopolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Pochat (1983), Der Symbolbegriff in der Asthetik und Kunstwissenschaft, Köln: DuMont Buchverlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Rudolph and B.O. Küppers (editors) (1995), Kulturkritik nach Ernst Cassirer, Hamburg: Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Schiemann (1998), The Loss of World in the Image. Origin and Development of the Concept of Image in the Thought of Hermann von Helmholtz and Heinrich Hertz, in: D. Baird-R.I.G. Hughes-A. Nordmann (editors) (1998), pp. 25–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • M. Schlick (1918), Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre, Berlin: Springer.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • M. Schlick (1974), General Theory of Knowledge, transl. by A. Blumenberg, Vienna: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • M. Schlick (1938) Gesammelte Aufsätze 1926–1936, hrsg. von F. Waismann, Wien, Gerold; english translation: Philosophical Papers, edited by H. Mulder and B. van de Velde-Schlick, 2 vols., Dordrecht: Reidel (1978/1979).

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Schröder (1966), Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik (1890), vol. I, New York: Chelsea Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Tonelli (1987), Da Leibniz a Kant. Saggi sul pensiero del Settecento, a cura di C. Cesa, Napoli: Prismi.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Trabant (1990), Traditionen Humboldts, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Trendelenburg (1857), Ueber Leibnizens Entwurf einer allgemeinen Charakteristik, in: Trendelenburg (1867), vol. III, pp. 1–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Trendelenburg (1867), Historische Beiträge zur Philosophie, vol. III, Berlin: Bethge.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. von Helmholtz (1903), Vorträge und Reden, 2 vols., Braunschweig: Vieweg und Sohn.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • H. von Helmholtz (1962), Treatise on Physiological Optics (1856–1867), 2 vols., edited by J.P.C. Southall, New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. von Helmholtz (1977), Epistemological Writings. The Paul Hertz/Moritz Schlick Centenary Edition of 1921 with Notes and Commentary by the Editors, newly transl. by M.F. Low, edited with an Introduction and Bibliography by R.S. Cohen and Y. Elkana, Dordrecht/Boston: Reidel Publishing Company.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • A.N. Whitehead (1958), Symbolism. Its Meaning and Effect (1928), London: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • L. Wittgenstein (1961), Notebooks (1914–1916), edited by G. von Wright and G.E. Ascombe, Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • L. Wittgenstein (1974), Tractatus logico-philosophicus (1921), transl. by D.F. Pears and B.F. McGuinness, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2002 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ferrari, M. (2002). Sources for the History of the Concept of Symbol from Leibniz to Cassirer. In: Ferrari, M., Stamatescu, IO. (eds) Symbol and Physical Knowledge. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-04855-9_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-04855-9_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-642-07474-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-662-04855-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics