Skip to main content

Gun Control

  • Chapter
Criminal Dilemmas

Part of the book series: Studies in Economic Theory ((ECON.THEORY,volume 12))

  • 179 Accesses

Abstract

As gun control is a controversial, emotional topic, it has become increasingly difficult to resolve. Should guns be limited or made illegal, or should the population be allowed to bear arms, as some argue is permitted by the US Constitution?294 The pros and cons for this debate are numerous. A sample of arguments from each side will be provided here. Then, they are analyzed in a game theoretic format to show how this analytic approach helps facilitate an understanding of the subject.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 74.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Reference

  1. The actual wording in the second amendment of the Constitution refers to the rights to form a militia and to bear arms within these groups. “A well regulated Militia being necessary to the security of a free State, the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed.” “The Supreme Court has stated that today’s militia is the National Guard.” U.S. Department of Justice, Federal Bureau of Investigation Home Page, “Three Myths Used Against Gun Control,” January 5, 1997

    Google Scholar 

  2. In Lott, and Mustard, 1/23/96, A8.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Lott, and Mustard, 1997, L

    Google Scholar 

  4. U.S. Department of Justice, [B], 1/5/97.

    Google Scholar 

  5. U.S. Department of Justice, [D], 1/5/97.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Reuters, 2/7/97, 12.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Don Kates refers to those who are completely opposed to the possession of firearms as “anti-gun.” See Kates, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  9. U.S Dept. of Justice, [G].

    Google Scholar 

  10. Kleck, 1991, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Secter, and McRoberts, 10/1/96.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Verhovek, 8/3/95, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Associated Press, 12/13/95.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Seelye, 4/1/95, 26.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Krauss, 2/25/97, A14.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Krauss, 2/25/97, A14.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Kleck, 1991, 6.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Polsby, and Brennen, 1995, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  20. The Economist, 4/15/95, 27.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cited in Polsby, and Brennen, 1995, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Seelye, 4/1/95, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  23. In Polsby and Brennen, 1995, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Kleck, 1991, 5. This finding is supported by Kates, 1991, who argued that the number of times per year that handguns are used in self defense slightly exceeds the estimated number of crimes attempted by or committed by handgun armed felons each year. p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Polsby and Brennen, 1995, 3and4.

    Google Scholar 

  26. The Economist, 4/15/95, 27.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Kates, 1991, 5. The limits of legal obligations of the police can be seen in: California Government Code 821, 845, 846, and 85, Illinois Rev. Stat. 4–102 construed in Stone v State. (Kates, fn 20.) Also in “Calogrides v City of Mobile, 475 So. 2d 560 (S. Ct. Ala. 1985) - quoting with approval from Weutrich v Delia, 155 N.J Super 324, 326, 382 A.2d 929, 930 (1978) `a public entity such as a municipality is not liable in tort for its failure to protect against the criminal propensity of third persons.” “ among others. (Kates, fn. 16)

    Google Scholar 

  28. Kates, 1991, 6.

    Google Scholar 

  29. There has been, however, an unfortunate lack of research and development on alternative forms of protection and self defense. Kates attributes this lack primarily to the political resistance on the part of those “numerous and influential segment of anti-gun advocates who disapprove of every form of private self protection.” He claims that the resulting political situation deters those from undertaking the costs of developing alternative forms of protection because of the fear that they will be banned. 1991, fn 6.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Kleck, 1991, 5.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Kates, 1991, 13–14. and Cook, 1986, 405and407.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Kleck, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Kates, 1991, fn. 87.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Kates, 1991, 16.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Polsby and Brennen, 1995, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ibid, 4.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Kates, 1991, fn. 51. “for instance, an experienced medical examiner comments that he has never seen or heard of a death occurring `by accident’ in cleaning a gun that did not turn out, on examination, to be either a suicide or a murder.” See also Rushford, Hirsch, Ford, and Adelson, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Heard, 2/7/97, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  43. See Olson, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Olson, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Olson, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Polsby and Brennen, 1995, 17.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Polsby and Brennen, 1995, 17.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Polsby and Brennen, 1995, 16.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Ibid, 17.

    Google Scholar 

  50. This assertion is not made lightly. Evidence suggests that firearms can be very effective both in aiding a criminal to successfully carry out his crime and also in aiding a victim to deter the criminal. In both cases, the weapon does not actually have to be used to be effective. If one party is armed and the other is not, the mere display of the gun may at times be sufficient to awe the other. See Kates, 1991, 12 and fn. 71.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Polsby and Brennen, 1995, 16–17.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Kates, 1991, 9.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Community punishment, whether ostracization or in other forms, should not be underestimated. The effect of this treatment has been used to argue against the imposition of “Megan’s Law”, a law which necessitates that a community be informed if a convicted sex offender will move into the area upon release from prison. The arguments against the law have centered around the issue that this requirement forces the offender to be “punished twice” for the same time. Thus, community action constitutes a formidable form of punishment.

    Google Scholar 

  54. It can be shown that if a player cheats another in a repeated PD game, then the other can respond with a strategy of Tit For Tat, TFT, or cheating in response to her opponent’s having cheated, or by cheating 2 times, 2TFT, in response, to punish, or by using the Grim Trigger strategy and always cheating against the original cheater. These strategies can be shown to deter a player from cheating. See Myerson, 1991 for examples of strategies.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Milgrom, North, and Weingast (1990) show that if information is perfect, i.e. if all members of a community share all of the information about the other members, then the using the strategy of ATFT (adjusted TFT) can produce cooperation. In Saari-Sieberg 1998, I show that even imperfect information, up to a certain limit, can help maintain cooperation in a community.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Weisheit, and Wells, 1996, 380. 35o Lott and Mustard, 1997, 3.chrw(133)[O]ne has to take seriously the possibility that `across-the-board’ gun control measures could decease the crime-control effects of noncriminal gun ownership more than they would decrease the crime-causing effects of criminal gun ownership.352

    Google Scholar 

  57. Kleck, 1991. 6–7.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Ibid, 7.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Verhovek, 8/3/95, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Lott and Mustard, 1997, 4.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Kates, 1991, 17–18.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Ibid, 18.

    Google Scholar 

  64. For instance, I may not feel the need for, and may even feel inconvenienced by a weapon in Sweden, but I may feel much more secure if I have one while walking through the Bronx in New York.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Kates, 1991, refers to this phenomena as “displacement” and claims that it does not add to the social good, because crime has not been deterred, rather it has just been moved to other victims.

    Google Scholar 

  66. The probability would be p=[R-C]/[R-C+1)].

    Google Scholar 

  67. This assumption is made for simplicity and does not significantly change results.

    Google Scholar 

  68. The new probability is p=2[R-C]/[R-C+D]. Note that if the probability of success in armed conflict were different, it would change only the magnitude of probability of armed victims necessary.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Note that this model does not include the criminal’s additional strategy of fighting in response to a victim’s actions. The model follows Kreps and Wilson (1982) and Selten’s ( 1975 ) CSP model. Additional strategies for the criminal will be taken up later in the chapter.

    Google Scholar 

  70. For proof, see Kreps and Wilson, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Kleck, 1991, 6.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Kates, 1991, 19–21.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Kates, 1991, 21.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Kates, 1991, 21.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  76. This occurs frequently enough to be a problem, see Kates, 1991. Some criminals harm their victims before their victims resist to prevent them from resisting later.

    Google Scholar 

  77. As the probability, s, increases that a criminal prefers, or will fight an armed victim, then if the payoffs to the victim are very low (in this case, death or injury) for armed conflict, then it can be shown that, for a time, some victims will be deterred from arming themselves. Eventually, beliefs may change and victims may arm themselves again, causing the beliefs of the criminals to change, leading many to avoid attack.

    Google Scholar 

  78. This claim comes from the fact that we can further extend the model to account for the possibility that the criminal will escalate violence even if the victim does not fight. If this possibility is included in the model, then the victim will be better off fighting.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Lott and Mustard, 1997, 18.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Ibid, 19.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Ibid

    Google Scholar 

  82. Ibid, 19–24.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Ibid, 19.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Ibid, 26. It should be noted here that, in reference to what I have argued earlier in the paper, some of these results arrive from aggregating data from rural and urban areas. Thus, the results could have errors.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Ibid, 29.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Ibid, 31.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Lott and Mustard, 1997, 35.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Graph found in Lott and Mustard, 1997, 35. I am grateful to John Lott for calling it to my attention.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Ibid, 39–43. Please refer to the paper for more detail and for other tests run by the authors.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Ibid, 51–62. The results from Arizona may have been affected by the fact that because the change in the law was recent, the authors were unable to control for all of the variables that they controlled for in other regressions.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Kates, 1991, 12.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Lott and Mustard, 1997, 19.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Ibid, 19.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Ibid, 62–64.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Please refer to Kleck, 1991, for more details about the relative strengths and weaknesses of the tests, and for the results.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Kleck, 1991, 6.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Lacayo, 1/15/96, 50.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Pooley, 1/15/96, 55.

    Google Scholar 

  102. The Economist, 1/6/96, 19.

    Google Scholar 

  103. The Economist, 8/3/94.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Ibid

    Google Scholar 

  105. Lott and Mustard, 1997, 18–62.

    Google Scholar 

  106. The Economist, 12/17/94, 23.

    Google Scholar 

  107. In a conversation, February, 1997, John Lott mentioned that training requirements can have a beneficial effect, but if they are too long or cost too much, they can decease the benefits of deterrence by provoking some people to decide not to obtain a weapon. I am grateful to him for the conversation and for the information.

    Google Scholar 

  108. Lott, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Polsby and Brennen, 1995, 6.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Herbert, 4/1/95.

    Google Scholar 

  111. Polsby and Brennen, 1995, 7.

    Google Scholar 

  112. Lott and Mustard, 1997, 36–37.

    Google Scholar 

  113. Polsby and Brennen, 1995, 5.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Melcer, 3/4/97, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  115. U.S Department of Justice, [E], 1/5/97.

    Google Scholar 

  116. U.S Department of Justice, [C], 1/5/97.

    Google Scholar 

  117. U.S Department of Justice[A], 1/5/97.

    Google Scholar 

  118. See Olson, 1965, for more detail on the collective action problem.

    Google Scholar 

  119. A simple analogy could be seen in pollution reduction. I may dislike pollution and may believe that we should take steps to reduce pollution, but may be resistant to the idea of purchasing a converter for, or discontinuing use of, my smog-producing car. If everyone has the same reaction, then pollution will continue or even grow.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Obviously, authorities are not going to perform daily checks to ensure that these rules are obeyed. Penalties could be applied, however, to those who do not conform to the rules. If, for instance, a person is accidentally shot due to the fact that the safety measures were not used, then the gun owner could be guilty of murder. This risk could serve to provide incentives to take precautions.

    Google Scholar 

  121. Kleck, 1991, 14–19.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Kleck, 1991, 18–19.

    Google Scholar 

  123. Lott and Mustard, 1997, 36.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Pooley, 1/15/96, 56.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Lacayo, 1/15/96, 53.

    Google Scholar 

  126. See Chapter 1 for more detail.

    Google Scholar 

  127. See Chapter 1 for more detail.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sieberg, K.K. (2001). Gun Control. In: Criminal Dilemmas. Studies in Economic Theory, vol 12. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-04543-5_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-04543-5_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-662-04545-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-662-04543-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics