Skip to main content

Dimensions of Moral Intuitions – Metaethics, Epistemology and Moral Psychology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Abstract

In everyday life we are permanently confronted with moral problems. But we are also faced with many difficulties and many different forms of how to come to a moral judgment. Modern moral psychology, as an interdisciplinary approach, tries to shed light on moral decision-making processes. Within philosophy it has been discussed since Hume’s sentimentalist approach to ethics what kind of moral judgment is the more convincing one – a judgment that relies on emotions or a judgment that reies on rational thinking. This debate nowadays heats up again as empirical data enters the philosophical realm. Psychologists, sociologists, neuroscientists and biologists deliver studies that seem to support the conviction that moral decision making actually does not have much to do with rational considerations – instead, it seems to be an intuitive process that depends on emotions instead of deliberation. In doing so, many researchers opt for a dual process theory that relies on implicit as well as explicit structures of reasoning. However, in many cases they reduce the explicit paths in their work. I will argue that this is due to the fact that different kinds of explanation levels are not kept apart thoroughly. I will start my considerations on the merits and problems of the recent developments in moral psychology from the epistemological point of view and distinguish this from a psychological and a normative understanding. In the light of these considerations I will show what kind of problems can occur through an analysis of Haidt’s social intuitionism and draw some conclusions on how we could elaborate a dual process theory that is theoretically informed as well as empirically supported.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (2000). Intention. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Appiah, A. (2008). Experiments in ethics. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J. A., & Chartrand, T. (1999). The unbearable automaticity of being. American Psychologist 54, 462–479.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chaiken, S. (1980). Heuristic versus systematic information processes and the use of source versus message cues in persuasion. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 39, 753–766.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christen, M., Vitacco, D. A., Huber, L., Harboe, J., Fabrikant, S. I., & Brugger, P. (2013). Colorful brains: 14 years of display practice in functional neuroimaging. NeuroImage, doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2013.01.068.

    Google Scholar 

  • Curtis, V. (2011). Why disgust matters. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, doi: 10.1098/rstb.2011.0165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorsey, D. (2006). A coherence theory of truth in ethics. Philosophical Studies 127(3), 493–523.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. (1984). Heuristic and analytic processes in reasoning. British Journal of Psychology 75, 451–468.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. B. T., & Frankish, K. (Eds.) (2009). In two minds: Dual processes and beyond. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1988). Realism, Mathematics and Modality. Philosophical Topics 16(1), 57–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, C. (2006). Is the emotional dog wagging its rational tail, or chasing it? Philosophical Explorations, doi: 10.1080/13869790500492680.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1992). Responsibility, Freedom and Reason. Ethics 102(2), 368–389.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, A. (2011). Metaethics: An introduction. Durham: Acumen Pub.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1967). The problem of abortion and the doctrine of double effect. Oxford Review 5, 5–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M. S., Bogen, J. E., & Sperry, R. W. (1996). Some functional effects of sectioning the cerebral commissures in man. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 48, 1765–1769.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gensler, H. J. (2011). Ethics: A contemporary introduction. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (2002). Wise choices, apt feelings: A theory of normative judgement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., & Todd, P. M. (1999). Fast and frugal heuristics: The adaptive toolbox. In G. Gigerenzer & P. M. Todd (Eds.), Simple heuristics that make us smart (pp. 3–34). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2003). Opinion: From neural 'is' to moral 'ought': what are the moral implications of neuroscientific moral psychology? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, doi: 10.1038/nrn1224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. D. (2007). The Secret Joke of Kant’s Soul. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral Psychology, Vol. 3: The Neuroscience of Morality: Emotion, Disease, and Development (pp. 35–79). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J., & Haidt, J. (2002). How (and where) does moral judgment work? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, doi: 10.1016/S1364-6613(02)02011-9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. D., Nystrom, L. E., Engell, A. D., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2004). The Neural Bases of Cognitive Conflict and Control in Moral Judgment. Neuron, doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2004.09.027.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An fMRI Investigation of Emotional Engagement in Moral Judgment. Science, doi: 10.1126/science.1062872.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenwald, A. G., & Banaji, M. R. (1995). Implicit Social Cognition: Attitudes, Self-Esteem, and Stereotypes. Psychological Review 102(1), 4–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunnell, J. G. (2007). Are we losing our minds?: Cognitive science and the study of politics. Political Theory 35(6), 704–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review (108), 814–834.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2006). The happiness hypothesis: Putting ancient wisdom and philosophy to the test of modern science. London: Arrow Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2013). The righteous mind: Why good people are divided by politics and religion. London et al.: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J., & Bjorklund, F. (2008). Social Intuitionists Answer Six Questions about Moral Psychology. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology, Vol.2: The cognitive science of morality: intuition and diversity (pp. 181–217). Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J., & Graham, J. (2007). When Morality Opposes Justice: Conservatives Have Moral Intuitions that Liberals may not Recognize. Social Justice Research, doi: 10.1007/s11211-007-0034-z.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J., & Hersh, M. A. (2001). Sexual Morality: The Cultures and Emotions of Conservatives and Liberals. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, doi: 10.1111/j.1559-1816.2001.tb02489.x.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J., Koller, S. H., & Dias, M. G. (1993). Affect, culture, and morality, or is it wrong to eat your dog? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65(4), 613–628.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J., McCauley, C., & Rozin, P. (1994). Individual differences in sensitivity to disgust: A scale sampling seven domains of disgust elicitors. Personality and Individual Differences, doi: 10.1016/0191-8869(94)90212-7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. M. (1981). Moral thinking: Its levels, method, and point. Oxford, New York: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1977). The nature of morality: An introduction to ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, S. (2009). The moral landscape: How science could determine human value. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helion, C., & David, A. P. (2015). Beyond Dual-Processes: The Interplay of Reason and Emotion in Moral Judgment. In J. Clausen & N. Levy (Eds.), Handbook of neuroethics (pp. 109–125). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2005). Ethical intuitionism. Basingstoke, New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D., Norton, M. J., & Norton, D. F. (2007). A treatise of human nature: A critical edition. Oxford, New York: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. (2013). The evolutionary debunking of morality. In J. Feinberg & R. Shafer-Landau (Eds.), Reason and responsibility: Readings in some basic problems of philosophy (pp. 527–537). Boston: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G. (2011). Evolutionary Debunking Arguments. Noûs, doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0068.2010.00770.x.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G., & Shackel, N. (2010). Methodological Issues in the Neuroscience of Moral Judgement. Mind & Language, doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0017.2010.01401.x.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2012). Thinking, fast and slow. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennett, J., & Fine, C. (2009). Will the real moral judgment please stand up? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 12(1), 77–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, G. A. (1999). Sources of power: How people make decisions. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. M., & Nichols, S. (2008). Experimental philosophy. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liao, M. (2011). Bias and Reasoning: Haidt's Theory of Moral Judgment. In T. Brooks (Ed.), New waves in ethics (pp. 108–127). Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire, New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moll, J., de Oliveira-Souza, R., Eslinger, P. J., Bramati, I. E., Mourão-Miranda, J., Andreiuolo, P. A., et al. (2002). The Neural Correlates of Moral Sensitivity: A Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging Investigation of Basic and Moral Emotions. The Journal of Neuroscience 22(7), 2730–2736.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia ethica. Cambridge: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. (2004). Sentimental rules: On the natural foundations of moral judgment. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.84.3.231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petrinovich, L. F. (2000). The cannibal within (Evolutionary foundations of human behavior). New York: Aldine de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petty, R. E., & Cacioppo, J. T. (1986). Communication and Persuasion: Central and Peripheral Routes to Attitude Change. New York, NY: Springer New York.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pizarro, D. A., & Bloom, P. (2003). The intelligence of the moral intuitions: A comment on Haidt (2001). Psychological Review, doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.110.1.193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pizarro, D., Inbar, Y., & Helion, C. (2011). On Disgust and Moral Judgment. Emotion Review, doi: 10.1177/1754073911402394.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2006). The Emotional Basis of Moral Judgements. Philosophical Explorations (9), 29–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2007a). Can Moral Obligations Be Empirically Discovered? Midwest Studies in Philosophy, doi: 10.1111/j.1475-4975.2007.00148.x.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2007b). The emotional construction of morals. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pust, J. (2014). Intuition. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/intuition/. Accessed 11.11.2014.

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricken, F. (2013). Allgemeine Ethik (5th edn, Urban-Taschenbücher, Vol. 348). Stuttgart: Kohlhammer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (1930). The right and the good. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saltzstein, H. D., & Kasachkoff, T. (2004). Haidt's Moral Intuitionist Theory: A Psychological and Philosophical Critique. Review of General Psychology, doi: 10.1037/1089-2680.8.4.273.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, L. F. (2009). Reason and Intuition in the Moral Life: A Dual Process Account of Moral Justification. In J. B. T. Evans & K. Frankish (Eds.), In two minds: Dual processes and beyond (pp. 335–354). Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schleim, S. (2008). Gedankenlesen: Pionierarbeit der Hirnforschung (1st edn, Telepolis). Hannover: Heise.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, D. (2015): Intuition und Emotion. In: Zeitschrift für Didaktik der Philosophie und Ethik (2).

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (2000). A defense of motivational externalism. Philosophical Studies 97(3), 267–291.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008). Moral psychology. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2011). Moral Skepticism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/skepticism-moral/. Accessed 11.11.2014.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skerry, A. E., & Saxe, R. (2014). A Common Neural Code for Perceived and Inferred Emotion. Journal of Neuroscience, doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.1676-14.2014.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (1759). The theory of the moral sentiments. Edinburgh: A. Millar; A. Kincaid & J. Bell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1995). The moral problem. Oxford, UK; Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Svavarsdottir, S. (1999). Moral Cognitivism and Motivation. Psychological Review 108(2), 161–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (1986a). Killing, Letting Die, and the Trolley Problem. In W. Parent (Ed.), Rights, restitution, and risk: Essays, in moral theory (pp. 78–93). Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (1986b). The Trolley Problem. In W. Parent (Ed.), Rights, restitution, and risk: Essays, in moral theory (pp. 94–116). Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turiel, E., Hildebrandt, C., & Wainryb, C. (1991). Judging social issues: Difficulties, inconsistencies, and consistencies. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. K. (1996). Living high and letting die: Our illusion of innocence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1981). Internal and External Reasons. In Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers, 1973-1980 (pp. 101–113). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Cordula Brand .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer Fachmedien Wiesbaden

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Brand, C. (2016). Dimensions of Moral Intuitions – Metaethics, Epistemology and Moral Psychology. In: Brand, C. (eds) Dual-Process Theories in Moral Psychology. Springer VS, Wiesbaden. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-658-12053-5_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics